Bill Weintraub

MANHOOD: A Reductional, Functional, Teleological, Incantational, and, above all, Sanctional -- Lexicon

Hi guy.

Welcome to Biblion Tetarton -- Book IV -- of Manhood: A Lexicon.

My name is Bill Weintraub, and I'm the creator of The Man2Man Alliance and Ares is Lord websites, and the author of Manhood: A Lexicon.

Manhood: A Lexicon is, basically, a book -- masquerading as a webpage.

And, like any book, it's best read from the beginning.

So -- I strongly encourage you to read, if you haven't already, the Prefatory Note and Prolegomena to Manhood: A Lexicon ;

And then Biblion Proton ;

Followed by Biblion Deuteron and Biblion Triton.

It's important that you read that material, and in that order:

Doing so will greatly aid your understanding of the material you encounter in Biblion Tetarton and the rest of Manhood: A Lexicon.

Also:

Biblion Tetarton -- Book IV -- is divided into sections:

Again, it's important that you read all five sections, and in the order given.

Finally:

Because Biblion Tetarton -- Book IV -- is long, and because some people have slower internet connections than others, the Book occupies two separate files online.

This page contains the first three sections of Biblion Tetarton.

Please read those first.

At the end of Section III -- ARES - EROS - AGON : Fighting Manhood and Manly Love, there's a link which will take you to the last two sections of Book IV.

In addition, you can access the last two sections of Biblion Tetarton either by clicking here ;

Or simply by using this List of Contents:

And -- if you have a fast internet connection, you can access the entirety of Biblion Tetarton by clicking here.

Bill Weintraub

July 20, 2013







MANHOOD: A LEXICON

BIBLION TETARTON
FIGHT IS THE FATHER OF ALL

By Bill Weintraub

MANHOOD: A LEXICON

BIBLION TETARTON
FIGHT IS THE FATHER OF ALL
Warriors and Warriordoms : The Ubiquity of Fighting Manhood

By Bill Weintraub

ςo -- now that we've identified Manhood, Fighting Manhood, with Moral Beauty, Goodness, Nobility, Excellence, Valour, and Worth ; looked at Manhood as the Primal Love, the Highest Value, and Good in Itself ; and begun to understand the process of UN-forgetting that same Absolute Manhood, that Supreme Fighting Manhood --

it's time to ask:

Is Fighting Manhood -- in the form of Struggle and Strife -- Fighting -- Fighting between Men who are, as famed classicist Werner Jaeger says, Struggling to Perfect their Manhood --

Is the Struggle of Manhood Against Manhood, the Fight of Fighting Manhood Against Fighting Manhood -- "the Father of All?"

Because, you see, "Fight is the Father of All" is a saying attributed to the Greek philosopher Heraclitus, who died a few years before Sokrates was born, and so is known as a "pre-Socratic."

In order to answer that question, I need to make some things clear to you, things which should be clear to you already but which, I can tell from what you say to me, are not.

First off, the ancient Greek world -- and the ancient Roman world and the ancient Keltic and Teutonic and Persian etc worlds -- were ALL Warriordoms:

They were all Masculinist and Martial cultures in which the Warrior, and his way of life, was supreme.

And they were, all, and as I've already said in the Prolegomena -- Dominant Cultures -- meaning that they called the shots, they determined what was normative and what wasn't.

Again: Warriordoms were Dominant Cultures -- it was their norms, their standards of behavior and belief, which mattered.

Just so that's really really and crystal clear, let's say it one more time:

Warriordoms were Dominant Cultures -- it was Warrior norms, Warrior standards of behavior and belief, which mattered.

And those Warrior standards of behavior and belief centered, as you've seen, on Fighting Manhood.

That being the case -- and keeping in mind the distinction, discussed in Biblion Deuteron, between the World of Becoming and the World of Being --

ALL MEN of that era lived in a sensible realm -- a world of becoming -- which was a WARRIORDOM -- that is, which centered on Fighting Manhood.

For the Greeks, that Fighting Manhood was expressed in Fight Sport -- nude and unarmed -- and on the battlefield.

Often, as you saw in our discussion of Timé, Fighting on the battlefield was nude also.

But it was armed -- and therefore deadly.

So -- for the Greeks, Fighting was sometimes armed and sometimes not.

For peoples like the Kelts and the Romans, Fighting was usually armed.

There persisted, after Rome conquered Greece, and in the Greco-Roman world, a tradition of Nude Fight Sport --


Imperial Roman Pankratiasts and Boxers

but what mattered to the Romans -- was knowing how to Fight -- with sword and shield.

But -- regardless of the particulars of how individual Men Fought in the World of Becoming:

The World of Being of virtually ALL MEN was a Warrior Kosmos -- governed by Warrior Ideas, Forms, Essences, and Ideals -- most especially, Fighting Manhood, which was identified with Moral Beauty, Goodness, Virtue, Valour, Courage, Nobility, Prowess, Excellence, Righteousness, and Worth.

As you've seen, and focusing on the Greeks, in the Prolegomena and Bibilon Proton -- and the following Biblia as well.

We today, by contrast, no longer live in Warriordoms -- and, as a consequence, only a very few Men have managed to UN-forget their Manhood and commune with it -- in the Warrior World of Being.

But that was NOT so in the ancient world.

And I know that most of you won't believe me -- because I know for example that to convince even a guy like NW, a guy who's actually trained, and fought, in Fight Sport -- I know that to convince him of the simple fact, for example, that armed single-combat, one-on-one combat with weapons -- was normative in the ancient world of the Romans and the Kelts -- is a struggle.

He just doesn't or can't believe or accept it.

But -- I'm correct.

So -- let's take a little time to look at an encounter between two Warriors, one Keltic, the other Roman -- an armed single-combat -- in 359 BC, as described by classicist JE Lendon.


Fighting Manhood.

The Greek word is Areté.

The Latin word is Virtus.

This is a bit of what classicist J E Lendon, whose work we examined in The Secret Craft of Warriorhood, says about Virtus:

Virtus was the root value of Romans of the middle Republic -- Romans wore iron rings to symbolize it -- and like the martial excellence [areté] of the Greeks, virtus was par excellence a competitive quality.

. . .

It was the fiery ambition of Romans, especially young Roman aristocrats, to excel those around them in virtus that led them to seek out single combat.

. . .

[In 359 BC] a vast company of Gauls was camped in the Pomptine country south of Rome. The Gauls, Rome's most feared enemy, had sacked the city [thirty] years earlier, vagrant armies of Gauls wandering over Italy brought frequent panics, and the Gallic attacks had brought Rome's neighbors to the north, the haughty and refined Etruscans, to the verge of destruction. The Roman army marched against the Gauls, but the Roman war leaders, the consuls, were alarmed by the number and strength of the ancestral foe.

. . .

[A] gigantic Gaul -- "naked except for his shield, two swords, torque [metal collar], and arm-rings" -- had challenged the Romans to send forth a champion to face him. "No one dared because of his size and savage appearance. Then the Gaul began to laugh at them and stick out his tongue." Offended at the insult to his country, the young Titus Manlius answered the challenge, and when the Gaul came on singing, the Roman rammed the barbarian's shield with his own, driving him back and throwing him off balance, eventually getting under his guard and stabbing him in the chest and then the shoulder with his sword. "When he had overthrown him, he cut off his head, dragged off his torque, bloody as it was, and put it around his own neck. For this act he and his posterity bore the nickname 'Torquatus,' " the Torqued one.

~J E Lendon, Soldiers and Ghosts: A History of Battle in Classical Antiquity

So let's talk about the Gauls -- that is, the Kelts -- and the Romans a bit.

Lendon says that the Kelt was "naked except for his shield, two swords, torque [metal collar], and arm-rings."

And that's correct.

The Kelts, like the Greeks, Fought Nude.

This is a Greek sculpture of a Keltic Warrior:

This is also Greek:

The Kelts, like the Greeks, Fought Nude.

Which means that whatever the Keltic word for Timé -- Worth -- may have been -- Nude Combat added to it.

To a Kelt, Fighting Nude added to his Worth.

Which is Manhood.

Now: these are torques -- the gold collars which the Kelts wore:

And then we have this artist's conception:

The central figure in this battle scene could well be the Keltic Champion who taunted Titus Manlius:

Notice his torque, his arm-rings, his sword and shield, and of course his nudity, very much as the Roman historian has described:

This is a Hellenistic sculpture of a dying Celtic Warrior -- the Man Titus Manlius fought may well have looked like this Man:

Here are two more nude Kelts, attacking and killing Romans:

And now we fast forward about 500 years, from the time of Titus Manlius in 359 BC to about 150 AD.

Gaul has been conquered and Romanized, and these are Romanized Kelts who are in the Roman army.

But they're still, in good Keltic fashion, collecting the heads of their enemies:

Because that what the Kelts of Gaul did -- before the Romans "civilized" them.

They engaged in one-on-one armed combats with their enemies, and, when victorious, cut off the head of the dead man, pickled it, and kept it on a shelf in their homes -- which were huts.

That's what the Kelts did.

They engaged in one-on-one armed combat.

Among themselves.

And with Romans and other foreign foes.

Now:

While I know this tale of Titus Manlius and the Kelt will bother some folks of Keltic extraction --

we need to see what was happening in context.

This was hundreds of years before Julius Caesar conquered Gaul.

At this point, the Kelts were the aggressors.

They'd invaded Italy, they'd sacked Rome, and they were rampaging.

They were dangerous and they were scary.

The average Kelt was physically larger than the average Roman, the Romans could not be said to be technologically more advanced than the Kelts -- indeed, the Roman sword, the gladius, was Keltic in origin -- and the Kelts were fierce fighters.

So -- when Titus Manlius met the Keltic challenger, he was demonstrating -- both Men were demonstrating -- Virtus -- Martial Courage -- which is Fighting Manhood.

In the context, as Lendon says, of

a heroic culture not too far distant from the military culture depicted in the [great Greek national epic, the] Iliad but even more ceremonious and ritualized.

Which means that not just the two cultures, Greek and Roman -- but the *three* cultures -- Greek, Roman, and Kelt -- were very similar.

Very very similar.

As are many -- almost certainly most -- Warrior cultures.

Warriordoms.

Which at one time covered the world.

The young Warriors in those cultures were aggressively competitive.

Lendon:

[the young Roman Warrior] regarded his comrades as his competitors in aggressive bravery.

"Aggressive Bravery" --

Prof Lendon really has a way with words, and "Aggressive Bravery" is a terrific characterization of a Manly trait:

Like Brave Beauty, Aggressive Bravery is another definer of and marker for Manliness -- for Fighting Manhood.

And, Lendon adds:

Youth in the Roman tradition is ferox, ferocious; and embodies furor, savage passion.

Thus the Aggressiveness of young Men at War.



The Romans of the Republic had a problem balancing the Aggressive Bravery of Virtus -- Fighting Manhood -- with disciplina -- staying within the phalanx as ordered.

Because their aggressively brave young Warriors would break ranks to seek out One-on-One Combat with aggressively brave Warriors from the opposing force.

Lendon:

The Romans believed "that for young men to disobey [that is, break ranks] and fight against orders was justly punishable but at the same time right and natural" -- an expression of Virtus -- Manhood -- Martial Courage -- Manly Excellence -- Manly Goodness -- Manly Virtue.

So -- To the Romans, and clearly to the Kelts and Greeks as well, what the Romans called Virtus was "right and natural," a right and natural expression of the young Warrior's innate Fighting Manhood, Aggressive Bravery, Moral Beauty, Brave Beauty -- in the service of his country, his family, his friends, his ideals -- and himself.


Do you understand?

At one time, all the world was a Warriordom -- or, if you prefer --

Competing WarriordomS -- plural.

Greek, Macedonian, Roman, Kelt, Teuton, Dacian, Scythian, Persian, etc.

ALL MEN lived in Warriordoms.


And when those Men met, they Fought.

Because:

The World of Being -- the ideational world -- of virtually ALL of those MEN was a Warrior Kosmos -- governed by Warrior Ideas, Forms, Essences, and Ideals -- most especially, Fighting Manhood, which was identified with Moral Beauty, Goodness, Virtue, Valour, Courage, Nobility, Prowess, Excellence, Righteousness, and Worth.

And that comes through repeatedly in ancient literature, including in the writing of Plato, who we today think of not as a Warrior, but as a philosopher.

Nevertheless, he was a Warrior as well, and that's apparent in his writing, with its frequent focus on the training and lives of Fighting Men.

However -- before talking about Plato the Warrior, let's fast forward a couple thousand years so as to make clear to you that the culture of sword-fighting and one-on-one armed combat described by Prof Lendon and myself -- persisted for centuries -- long after Hellenism -- what Christians call "paganism" -- had been done in by those same Christians.

So -- let's take a brief look at John Milton, a Puritan poet and pamphleteer, and a member of Cromwell's anti-monarchist government, who lived from 1608 to 1674, and who created one of the greatest poems in the English language, Paradise Lost.

But long before he published, in the 1660s, that poem, he'd written, in 1644, when he was thirty-five years old, a Tractate of Education.

His plan for educating English youth under the new Puritan government is in many ways, including in its emphasis on single-gender living and communal life, quite Spartan ; relies heavily on Classical Greek writers; seeks to produce Men who are Virtuous, Valorous, and, as he'd say, Heroick; and emphasizes Fighting with Swords -- and Wrestling:

Now will be worth the seeing what exercises and recreations may best agree, and become these studies.

The course of Study hitherto briefly describ'd, is, what I can guess by reading, likest to those ancient and famous Schools of Pythagoras, Plato, Isocrates, Aristotle and such others, out of which were bred up such a number of renown'd Philosophers, Orators, Historians, Poets and Princes all over Greece, Italy, and Asia, besides the flourishing Studies of Cyrene and Alexandria. But herein it shall exceed them, and supply a defect as great as that which Plato noted in the Common-wealth of Sparta ; whereas that City train'd up their Youth most for War, and these in their Academies and Lycaeum, all for the Gown, this institution of breeding which I here delineate, shall be equally good both for Peace and War.

Therefore about an hour and a half ere they eat at Noon should be allowed them for exercise and due rest afterwards : but the time for this may be enlarged at pleasure, according as their rising in the morning shall be early.

The Exercise which I commend first is the exact use of their Weapon [sword], to guard and to strike safely with edge, or point ; this will keep them healthy, nimble, strong, and well in breath, is also the likeliest means to make them grow large and tall, and to inspire them with a gallant and fearless courage, which being temper'd with seasonable Lectures and Precepts to them of true Fortitude and Patience, will turn into a native and heroick valour, and make them hate the cowardice of doing wrong. They must be also practis'd in all the Locks and Gripes of Wrastling, wherein English men were wont to excel, as need may often be in fight to tug or grapple, and to close. And this perhaps will be enough, wherein to prove and heat their single strength.

The interim of unsweating themselves regularly, and convenient rest before meat may both with profit and delight be taken up in recreating and composing their travail'd spirits with the solemn and divine harmonies of Musick heard or learnt . . .

~ text from archive.org

So -- the duel between Titus Manlius and the Kelt took place in 359 BC.

Yet, and literally, two millenia later -- two thousand and three years, to be exact -- John Milton is still talking about teaching youths to be proficient in swordsmanship, and in Wrestling, "as need may often be in fight to tug or grapple, and to close."

The Spartans -- and other ancient Greeks -- would have agreed.

So you can see that the culture of one-on-one sword Fighting and Wrestling -- had persisted long beyond the ancient world.

That doesn't mean, however, guys, that the Men of Milton's time would have thought as did the Men of Plato's and Plutarch's.

Christianity had greatly changed the way Men thought.

Just think, for example, of the ubiquitous Nudity of Ancient Men -- and how Christianity had shamed and legislated that -- out of existence.

As it had the True and Valorous Love of Fighting Man for Fighting Man.

So -- what concerns us here is the Pristine World of Flesh and Spirit -- which preceded Christianity's anti-masculinist shame, guilt, and oppression of the Male.

Which means it's time to get back to the pre-Christian, Manly, Ares and Eros worshipping, Warriordoms of the ancient world.


I said, regarding the Men of those ancient Warriordoms, that they Fought -- frequently.

Because:

The World of Being -- the ideational world -- of virtually ALL of those MEN was a Warrior Kosmos -- governed by Warrior Ideas, Forms, Essences, and Ideals -- most especially, Fighting Manhood, which was identified with Moral Beauty, Goodness, Virtue, Valour, Courage, Nobility, Prowess, Excellence, Righteousness, and Worth.

And that comes through repeatedly in ancient literature, including in the writing of Plato, who we today think of not as a Warrior, but as a philosopher.

Nevertheless, he was a Warrior as well, and that's apparent in his writing, with its frequent focus on the training and lives of Fighting Men.

For example, there's Plato's statement in the Timaeus, a book written after the Republic, that having designed his ideal Republic, what he would most like to see is how that Republic performs at War:

Socrates
The main part of the discourse I delivered yesterday was concerned with the kind of constitution which seemed to me likely to prove the best, and the character of its citizens.

Timaeus
And in truth, Socrates, the polity you described was highly approved by us all.

Socrates
Did we not begin by dividing off the class of land-workers in it, and all other crafts, from the class of its defenders?

Timaeus
Yes.

Socrates
And when, in accordance with Nature, we had assigned to each citizen his one proper and peculiar occupation, we declared that those whose duty it is to fight in defence of all must act solely as Guardians of the State, in case anyone from without or any of those within should go about to molest it; and that they should judge leniently such as are under their authority and their natural friends, but show themselves stern in battle towards all the enemies they encounter.

Timaeus
Very true.

Socrates
For we said, as I think, that the soul of the Guardians ought to be of a nature at once spirited and philosophic in a superlative degree, so that they might be able to treat their friends rightly with leniency and their foes with sternness.

Timaeus
Yes.

Socrates
And what of their training? Did we not say that they were trained in gymnastic [nude training, much of it in Fight Sport], in music, and in all the studies proper for such men?

Timaeus
Certainly.

Socrates
And it was said, I believe, that the men thus trained should never regard silver or gold or anything else as their own private property; but as auxiliaries, who in return for their guard-work receive from those whom they protect such a moderate wage as suffices temperate men, they should spend their wage in common and live together in fellowship one with another, devoting themselves unceasingly to virtue [areté -- Manhood], but keeping free from all other pursuits.

Plat. Tim. 17c-18b, translated by Lamb.

So -- Plato spends a lot of time describing a communal way of training and of life for his Guardians, a training and way of life very similar to that of the Spartans; and says that the Guardians are to live communally, and free of private property, thus facilitating among them both fellowship and unceasing devotion to Virtue -- which is Manhood.

Think about that.

Plato is saying that Warriors who live together, free of private property -- and of wives and children too, by the way -- will live in fellowship and unceasing devotion -- to Manhood.

Which, remember, is an ideal.

Plato then goes on to say, via Sokrates, that

[S]uppose, for instance, that on seeing beautiful creatures, whether works of art or actually alive but in repose, a man should be moved with desire to behold them in motion and vigorously engaged in some such exercise as seemed suitable to their physique; well, that is the very feeling I have regarding the State we have described. Gladly would I listen to anyone who should depict in words our State contending against others in those struggles which States wage; in how proper a spirit it enters upon war, and how in its warring it exhibits qualities such as befit its education and training in its dealings with each several State whether in respect of military actions or in respect of verbal negotiations.

~Plat. Tim. 19b

Plato's concept of Manhood, as expressed here, is the ancient concept of Manhood and it's absolutely correct.

Men, like other creatures, he says, should be

vigorously engaged in some such exercise as seemed suitable to their physique

And for Men, of course, that's Fighting.

Men, properly trained -- which includes training in Fight Sport -- and educated, then create the ideal State, which contends

against others in those struggles which States wage . . . war and warring

Indeed, throughout the Republic, Plato, in describing the education of his Guardians, his Warrior caste, refers specifically to the traditional physical training, the nude physical training, the gymnastika -- from gymnos (γυμνος), nude -- which was practised throughout Greece at the palaistrai (παλαιστραι), and which Plato says will make his Warriors "athletes of war" [athletes polemos αθλητης πολεμος].


Ephebes -- Plato's "Athletes of War" -- train at the Palaistra

Why was war so important to Plato?

The short answer is that he was an ancient Man.

And for Men like himself, war wasn't something which took place far away, overseas, carried out by drones and bombs and helicopters.

It wasn't.

War was always near, it was fought, more often than not, face-to-face and hand-to-hand, and the loser in a war was likely to be either killed or enslaved -- as would be his entire family, women and children too, and the rest of his fellow citizens.

So -- war -- and the ability to fight -- mattered.

Consider, for a moment and in that light, Plato's early years, not as an inquisitive youth nor scion of a wealthy and politically well-connected family nor brilliant student -- but as an Athlete-Warrior, and as described by the very hard-headed classicist Paul Shorey.

Let's begin by noting that the name "Plato" probably means "broad-shouldered"; and that there is, says Shorey, "a tradition of athletic victories" attributed to him.

Whether that tradition is correct or not, we know that Plato, as a boy and youth, would have trained at the palaistra and, like Xenophon's Autolycus and Sokrates' Charmides, Lysis, and Alkibiades, competed in athletics nude -- and that the bulk of the training and competition would have been in Fight Sport -- Wrestling, Boxing, and Pankration.

Along with what we would call "track and field," which included the "hoplites dromos" -- a race run genitally nude, but in hoplite armor:

Then there's Plato's military service.

Plato is thought to have been born in 427 BC -- which means that he lived through much of the Peloponessian War, and that he would have come of age in 409 BC -- when he was 18 -- and would have "entered as an ephebos [a recruit aged 18 to 20] the calvary which guarded much of the immediate environment [of Athens] against Spartan raids" from the "thirteen miles distant [Spartan] fortress of Dekeleia."

He would then "have fought in an undetermined battle of Megara [perhaps also in 409 BC], in which, he says in the Republic [368a], his brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus distinguished themselves."

In 406 BC, Plato would "have served in the fleet at the battle of Arginusae, where the Athenian victory was marred by the failure to recover the bodies of the dead in the storm that followed."

In 405 BC, Plato, along with his fellow citizens, would have learned of the annihilation of the Athenian fleet at Aegospotami and the approach of the Spartan fleet and army of occupation, and would have had to wonder, like any citizen of a defeated city-state, if he was going to be killed and his family and friends enslaved by the victors.

Think I'm making that up?

I'm not:

[The Spartan admiral] Lysander, after the three thousand Athenians whom he had taken prisoner [at Aegospotami] had been condemned to death by the special council of [Spartan] allies, calling Philocles, the [Athenian] general, asked him what punishment he thought should be visited upon him for having given his fellow-citizens such counsel regarding Greeks.

[Philocles "had ordered the crews of two captured [Spartan-allied] triremes to be thrown over a precipice"; and, according to Xenophon, had sponsored and/or supported a decree in the Athenian Assembly mandating that the right hand (Scott-Kilvert says it was the right thumb) of every Spartan and Spartan-allied prisoner of war be cut off.]

But he [Philocles], not one whit softened by his misfortunes, bade him [Lysander] not play the prosecutor in a case where there was no judge, but to inflict, as victor, the punishment he would have suffered if vanquished. Then, after bathing and putting on a rich robe, he went first to the slaughter and showed his countrymen the way, as Theophrastus writes. After this, Lysander sailed to the various cities, and ordered all the Athenians whom he met to go back to Athens, for he would spare none, he said, but would slaughter any whom he caught outside the city.

He took this course, and drove them all into the city together, because he wished that scarcity of food and a mighty famine should speedily afflict the city, in order that they might not hinder him by holding out against his siege with plenty of provisions.

~Plut. Lys. 13.2, translated by Perrin.

. . .

And now, when he [Lysander] learned that the people of Athens were in a wretched plight from famine, he sailed into the Piraeus, [the port of Athens,] and reduced the city, which was compelled to make terms on the basis of his commands.

. . .

Lysander, accordingly, when he had taken possession of all the ships of the Athenians except twelve, and of their walls, on the sixteenth day of the month Munychion, the same on which they conquered the Barbarian in the sea-fight at Salamis, took measures at once to change their form of government.

And when the Athenians opposed him bitterly in this, he sent word to the people that he had caught the city violating the terms of its surrender; for its walls were still standing, although the days were past within which they should have been pulled down; he should therefore present their case anew for the decision of the authorities, since they had broken their agreements. And some say that in very truth a proposition to sell the Athenians into slavery was actually made in the assembly of the [Spartan] allies, and that at this time Erianthus the Theban also made a motion that the city be razed to the ground, and the country about it left for sheep to graze.

[Sounds harsh, doesn't it?

But the Athenians had actually done worse to other cities, and on a number of occasions.

For example, Perrin notes that

The island and city of Melos were captured and depopulated by the Athenians in the winter of 416-415 B.C.

The city of Scione, on the Chalcidic peninsula, was captured and depopulated by the Athenians in 421 B.C.

"depopulated" means the men were killed and the women and children sold into slavery.

So -- it's not surprising that the Spartans and their allies considered doing the same to the Athenians.

And remember what Prof Lendon said regarding Athens and Timé in our discussion of Timé and the Battle of Sphakteria in Biblion Proton:

the whole structure of honor in warfare had been cast down.

The whole structure of honor in warfare -- which in this case was by and large the Timé -- the Worth which accrued to a Man -- and a city -- through victory in Manly warfare, that is, in hand-to-hand combat -- had been "cast down" -- by the Athenians.

So: During the Peloponessian War, the Athenians were guilty both of murderously barbarous conduct towards other Greeks ; and of behavior which had the effect of destroying the structure and concept of honor in warfare among the Greeks --

Which is why, after the defeat at Aegospotami, the Athenians wondered, and with good reason, whether what they'd done to so many others -- would now be done to them.

But -- it wasn't, and for the most poetical of reasons, as Plutarch explains:]

Afterwards, however, when the [Spartan and allied] leaders were gathered at a banquet, and a certain Phocian sang the first chorus in the 'Electra' of Euripides, which begins with:

0 thou daughter of Agamemnon,
I am come, Electra, to thy rustic court,

all were moved to compassion, and felt it to be a cruel deed to abolish and destroy a city which was so famous, and produced such poets.

So then, after the Athenians had yielded in all points, Lysander sent for many flute-girls from the city, and assembled all those who were already in the camp, and then tore down the walls, and burned up the triremes, to the sound of the flute, while the allies crowned themselves with garlands and made merry together, counting that day as the beginning of their freedom.

~Plut. Lys. 15.4, translated by Perrin.

Plato then lived through many years of civil turmoil at Athens, including both the discreditable reign, in 403 BC, of the "Thirty Tyrants," some of whom were his relatives, and many of whom were killed by a resurgent democracy, and the trial and execution, in 399 BC, of Sokrates.

Also by the resurgent democracy.

Plato is then said to have fought in the Corinthian War of 395 to 387 BC.

Translation:

Plato was not some professorial wimp.

He was a broad-shouldered Warrior-Athlete who, like any other Greek of his generation, knew what war was ; and who saw service in several campaigns -- starting as an ephebe in 409, and continuing to 387 -- that is, for twenty-two years.

Not unusual for a citizen-soldier of a Greek city-state.

Which was, again and essentially, a Warriordom -- a Masculinist and Warrior Culture in which the most important element of a Man's Life was his Warrior Manhood, his Fighting Spirit, expressed in competitive athletics -- and war.

Sokrates, too, saw significant military action, though, because he was older than Plato, in different battles.

But they are well attested to in the literature.

So -- famous Greeks, famous Athenians, like Sokrates, Plato, Aeschylus, etc -- as well as virtually all ordinary Greek Men -- lived through -- and participated in -- a lot of Combat -- Struggle -- Contest -- Battle -- War -- Fight.



MANHOOD: A LEXICON

BIBLION TETARTON
FIGHT IS THE FATHER OF ALL
Father and King : Fighting Manhood is the Father and Author of All

By Bill Weintraub

It wouldn't be surprising then, given their history and the reality of their day-to-day lives, if many Greeks -- indeed most of them -- believed that Fight is the Father of All.

And, in fact --

"Fight is the Father of All" is a saying attributed to the Greek philosopher Heraclitus, who died a few years before Sokrates was born, and so is known as a "pre-Socratic."

To fully understand that saying, and its meaning for our Lexicon of Manhood and our own Manly Lives, we can start by coming back to NW's phrase : "Aggression and the beauty of guys who asserted that aggression".

For NW, and for me, the Beauty of Guys -- a Beauty which is not just physical but moral also -- a Moral Beauty -- has always been tied to Aggression.

That is, to Fighting Manhood.

As it was for the Greeks.

For the Greeks, Moral Beauty and Fighting Manhood are inextricably intertwined.

And reductionally and functionally -- the same.

In ancient Greece, such Fighting Manhood was often expressed in fiercely competitive -- "agonal" -- nude male athletics.

As Erich Segal points out in his Foreward to Waldo Sweet's Sport and Recreation in Ancient Greece.

Segal, who died in 2010, is best known as the author of the saccharine Love Story.

But in real life he was a Harvard-educated classicist who taught at Yale.

In other words, a person of formidable erudition.

In his Foreward to Sweet's book, Segal notes that our word "sport" carries with it the sense of levity.

That's not true of the Greeks.

Their word, AGON, is the root of our word -- agony.

Which in Greek is agonia, and which means, first and foremost, a struggle for victory.

  • Agonia : a contest, struggle for victory ; gymnastic exercise, wrestling

    αγωνια

So an Agon is a Struggle, and the word Agon, says Segal, can "refer to encounters ranging from duels to debates."

Similarly, the Greek word athlos, from which we derive our word athletics, "could mean a contest taking place in a stadium or on a battlefield."

The idea of Fight as the Father of Everything permeated Greek life.

Segal:

Indeed, to some historians -- notably the Swiss Jakob Burkhardt (1818 - 1897) -- this "agonal drive" was the key to understanding an entire mentality. In his unequivocal words, "All Greek life was animated by this principle."

So -- let's look more closely at Heraclitus and what he actually said.

First off, I first took the phrase "Fight is the father of everything" -- (which Segal expressed as "Strife is the father of everything") -- from Erich Segal's Foreward, and shortened it, and with good reason, as you'll see, to "Fight is the Father of All."

And as I said above, that phrase comes from the Greek philosopher Heraclitus, who was a pre-Socratic -- he died a few years before Sokrates was born, and his work has come down to us in fragments.

And not only do we have only fragments, but the fragments are gnomic at best and often just plain cryptic.

So it's always a bit of a stretch to figure out just what he's saying.

But his basic ideas are usually clear enough, as is his fundamental idea, that "all is in flux" -- thus his best known adage, 'You can't step in the same river twice.'

And that of course is describing what Plato, about 150 years later, would call the World of Becoming -- in which change is constant.

So -- Segal extracted the idea that "Strife is the father of everything" from a fragment which I tracked down to this website -- and which, thankfully, has the Greek alongside it.

And there I found not one, but two fragments from Heraclitus which are relevant and more than relevant to our Manly Lexicon -- and to our Manly Lives.

The first is "Fragment 53," and it begins with an ancient Greek word -- Polemos -- which the site translates as "War."

That's technically accurate but -- to the people of our time -- somewhat misleading.

So -- let's start by looking at the definition of

We see that Polemos -- one of the most important words in the Greek language -- can be translated as battle, fight, war.

And that war is actually third in the list.

Which is why I frequently say that Ares is the God of Fight.

Because all of the Greek words variously translated as contest, conflict, struggle, strife, war, battle, combat, etc -- words like and including Agon αγων, Athlos αθλος, Eris ερις, Hamilla αμιλλα, Mache μαχη, Polemos πολεμος, Neikos νεικος, etc -- reduce -- to FIGHT.

Mache is defined as battle, FIGHT, combat.

Neikos is defined as strife, battle, FIGHT.

Polemos is defined as battle, FIGHT, war.

FIGHT.

Sometimes the Fight is unarmed ; and sometimes it's with weapons.

Sometimes the Fight is between masses of Men ; and sometimes it's one-on-one.

But it's always Fight and it's always about Fight.

Fight is the agonal principle and agonistic imperative.

Fight is the Father of All and King of All:

Fight is the Father of All and the King of All; and some He has made Gods and some Men, some bond [slave] and some Free.

Πολεμος παντων με&nu πατηρ εστι, παντων δε Βασιλευς, και τους μεν Θεους εδειξε τους δε ανθρωπους, τους μεν δουλους εποιηδε τους δε ελευθερους

~Heraclitus, Fragment 53, translated by Burnet.

"Fragment 53" is a profound statement by Heraclitus, with profound spiritual significance.

Because, and this is just for starters, it links Heraclitus (ca. 540 - 475 BC) -- who died about 50 years before Plato (ca. 427 - 348 BC) was born -- first with Plato himself, and then with Platonist and then Neo-Platonist philosophy as it developed between the death of Plato in 348 BC and the death of the great and Hellenizing Emperor Julian in 363 AD.

Specifically, Fragment 53 links Heraclitus with Plato's Idea of Good.

Because, of course, if Fight is the Father of All and King of All -- it takes on the universal attributes not only of what Plato would later call the World of Being -- but of the Idea of Good, the highest good, the Supreme Good -- itself.

So -- we're going to look at that -- and more.

But first, we need to consider another of Heraclitus' gnomic pronouncements -- which is today known as "Fragment 80":

It needs be aware of the war [πολεμος = polemos = battle, fight, war] being common and justice [δικη = dike] strife [ερις = eris] and everything becoming in accordance with strife and necessity.

Burnet translates that as "We must know that war is common to all and strife is justice, and that all things come into being through strife."

But actually Heraclitus doesn't say, strife is justice -- he says justice is strife -- which is more radical.

Heraclitus:

It needs be aware of the fight [polemos] being common and justice [dike] strife [eris] and everything becoming in accordance with strife and necessity.

Fight is common to All, Justice is Strife, and Everything comes into being -- be-comes -- in accordance with Strife.

Let's break that down:

  • Fight -- is common to All.

    We know that, and we know particularly that Fight and Fighting Spirit are common to All Men.

  • Justice is Strife.

    To the Greeks, that's correct.

    Think of Xenophon's Strife of Valour -- his Struggle of, for, and about Manhood -- which we discussed in, among other places, the Prologue to Biblion Proton.

    To Xenophon, that Struggle brings about and preserves the Justice -- the Eunomia and Homonoia -- the Manly Moral Order and Warrior Concord -- which constitute the Spartan state.

    Justice is Strife ; Strife is Justice.

  • Everything becomes in accordance with Strife.

    Everything becomes -- Heraclitus is talking about the realm of the senses, the World of Flux --

    In accordance with Strife -- Struggle, Strife, Combat, War, Fight.

    Strife, Struggle, Combat, War, Fight, then, is the Model -- the

    Strife, Struggle, Combat, War, Fight, then, is the Model -- the Paradeigma -- in my reading of Heraclitus -- which shapes everything -- in what Plato would later call the World of Becoming.

    And Plato further refined that formulation to say that what we sense, what we experience, in the World of Becoming are shadows, copies, and reflections of the Ideal Forms in the World of Being.

    Which means that --

    Everything comes into being -- becomes -- in accordance with Strife.

    Which, then, must be -- an Ideal Form, an Essence.

What, then, is Strife?

Is Strife -- Fighting Manhood?

Yes, and without question.

For --

In the human realms of both Becoming and Being, Strife is what we saw it to be in the Prologue to Biblion Proton of this Lexicon:

Strife is the Struggle, the Fight, between two Fighting Men, the Struggle of, for, and about Manhood.

Put more simply:

Strife is Fighting Manhood -- Fighting -- Fighting Manhood.

Fighting Manhood Against Fighting Manhood.

In the human sphere, Strife is the Struggle of Manhood Against Manhood.

The Fight of Manhood Against Manhood.

Strife is the Fight -- the ManFight -- *itself* -- the Struggle, the Combat, of Fighting Manhood Against Fighting Manhood.

Whose goal is to Perfect Manhood.

As Jaeger says:

Men Stuggling to Perfect Their Manhood.

Again -- think back to Xenophon's Strife of Valour -- which is really a Struggle of, for, and about Manhood.

What Marchant calls a Strife of Valour is really a Struggle between and among Young Fighting Men, a Fight of Manhood, a Fight for Manhood, a Fight about Manhood.

So -- in the sensible realm, the World of Becoming, Strife is Man Against Man.

And that Struggle and Strife of Man Against Man takes place within, between, and among the Warriordoms of the World of Becoming.

As Heraclitus says:

Everything becomes in accordance with Strife.

Including Man, who becomes Man in the Strife of Man Against Man.

Think back to the Prolegomena, and the story of Aristonicus the Harp-Player.

He became a Man in the Strife of Man Against Man.

By Fighting, Aristonicus left his old state of being, harp-player, and came, says Arrian, into a new state of being:

Man.

Aristonicus "was killed -- having fought however not like a harpist, but like a man."

In the original Greek, the verb Arrian uses is "gignomai" -- γιγνομαι -- which means -- "come into a new state of being."

The translator, de Selincourt, says "having fought however not like a harpist, but like a man."

But, what Arrian is really saying is that by Fighting, Aristonicus left the state of "harp-player," and came into a new state of being -- that of Man.

That of Brave, Good, and Noble -- Man.

And that's certainly how the Greeks saw it:

Fighting Makes the Man.

It Awakens the Man, as we often say in the Alliance, to his Manhood.

Fighting Awakens the Man to, it helps him UN-forget, his Manhood.

Manhood.

Which is the Willingness and Ability to Fight.

So -- in the Warriordom and Warriordoms, Man becomes Man -- Man can only become Man -- in the Struggle and Strife of Man Against Man.

Yet, and that said --

What's really going on -- is the Struggle and Strife -- the Fight -- of Manhood Against Manhood.

And that Manhood, that Fighting Manhood, ultimately resides, as we've seen, in the Warrior World of Being.

The Warrior Kosmos.

And because that Fighting Manhood resides in the Warrior World of Being, the Warrior Kosmos, where it is, de facto, the Idea of Good, it's both the Primal Love -- see Biblion Deuteron -- and the Primal Cause -- of the Warrior All:

    Making Fight -- again, functionally -- the Idea of Good, the Supreme Good.

    (πρωτην αιτιαν = proten aitian = First Cause, Primal Cause -- FIGHT is the Father of All and King of All -- FIGHT is the Primal Cause, the Idea of Good, the Supreme Good.)

    Plato uses the phrase

    αριστος των αιτιων = aristos ton aition = best, noblest, bravest, finest, morally best, and, therefore, Most Manly -- of causes.

    The First and Primal Cause is then the best, noblest, and bravest -- and, remember, aristos is one of our ARES words -- it's rooted in the First Notion of Goodness -- Fighting Manhood :

    From the same root [ARES] come areté, ari-, areion [better], aristos [best], the first notion of goodness being that of manhood, bravery in war; cf. Lat. virtus.

    ~Liddell and Scott, 1909

    We see then that aristos is defined as "bravest, noblest," and "morally finest" -- ALL of which mean and reduce to most Manly -- which in turn means that:

    The First Cause and Primal Cause is the most Manly -- of causes.

    And Manliness of course is a function and expression of Fighting Manhood.

    Translation:

    The First and Primal Cause is Fighting Manhood.

    Plato also says

    Now to discover the Maker and Father of this Universe [All] were a task indeed; and having discovered Him, to declare Him unto all men were a thing impossible.

    ~Plat. Tim. 28c, translated by Bury.

    The word Plato uses for Universe is "All" = pantos = πας = all -- the same word that Heraclitus uses for All = pantos = πας = all.

    So: what Plato actually says is "to discover the Maker and Father of All were a task indeed; and having discovered Him, to declare Him to All were a thing impossible."

    While Heraclitus says, "Fight is the Father of All and King of All."

    Heraclitus:

    Fight is the Father of All -- all the Kosmos -- and King of All -- all Men.

    Plato:

    To discover the Maker and Father of All -- all the Kosmos -- were a task indeed; and having discovered Him, to declare Him to All -- all Men -- were a thing impossible.

    There's a great symmetry between what these two great thinkers have said.

    Again, there's a great symmetry -- an intense congruence -- between what these Men have said.

    Which means, and, for the third time, functionally, that Plato and Heraclitus, though separated by perhaps a hundred years, are saying essentially the same thing:

    Fight is Father and King -- the Primal Cause -- of All ;

    Fighting Manhood is Father and Maker -- the Primal Cause -- of All.









So:

When we make the leap from Fight is the Father of All --

To Fighting Manhood is the Father of All --

What we're saying is that Fight and Fighting Manhood -- are synonymous.

Which they clearly are.





Fight -- and Fighting Manhood -- are synonymous.

Fight and Fighting Manhood are synonymous.

The Hallmark of Manliness -- the Hallmark of Manhood -- is, as my foreign friend says, Fighting Spirit.





Fighting Spirit.

Fighting Manhood.

Which is, according to Liddell and Scott's Greek-English Lexicon, the First Notion of Goodness.

And which, according to Lewis and Short's Latin Dictionary, is :

the sum of all the corporeal or mental excellences of man

MANHOOD --

By which Lewis and Short mean Fighting Manhood --

Is the Sum of All the Corporeal and Mental Excellences of Man.

Fighting Manhood is the Sum of All the Excellences of Man.

That definition dates from 1879.

And it tells us what MEN have believed and known to be True for literally tens of thousands of years:

That Fighting Manhood is the sum of all the corporeal and mental -- which includes the moral and spiritual -- excellences -- of Man.

And it's what guys like me and NW have said on our own -- for years:

That Fighting perfects the Male Body -- that's the corporeal part -- because that's what the Male Body was designed to do -- to FIGHT ;

And -- as we've seen throughout this Lexicon -- that Fighting Manhood defines mental and above all moral and spiritual excellence as well.

So -- Lewis and Short give a list:

strength, vigor; bravery, courage; aptness, capacity; worth, excellence, virtue

That's what Fighting Manhood is:

    Strength.

    Vigor.

    Bravery.

    Courage.

    Aptness.

    Capacity.

    Worth.

    Excellence.

    Virtue.

Fighting Manhood is the Sum of All the Excellences of Man:







And yet, ALL OUR LIVES Fighting Manhood has been denigrated and marginalized.

While the societal structures -- in places like ancient Greece -- which supported it and gave it its True and Manly form -- have been destroyed.

That's the problem.

And Men's Lives will never again be Right and Whole -- until that problem has been corrected.

And this statement has, once again, been acknowledged to be True:








Now:

Regarding Heraclitus' and Plato's formulations -- and what I said above about the great symmetry and intense congruence between them --

Fight is Father and King -- the Primal Cause -- of All ;

Fighting Manhood is Father and Maker -- the Primal Cause -- of All

That great symmetry and intense congruence is there because, as the Prolegomena and Biblion Proton make clear, there's both an intense culturally-mandated connection and an equally intense and essentially spiritual identification between and among Men, Fighting, Fighting Manhood, and what Plato calls the Idea of Good -- that is, Goodness, the Supreme Good, the Sanction, Virtue, Righteousness, Excellence, Moral Beauty, Moral Order -- and Manly Worth.

And if you've read the Prolegomena and Biblion Proton carefully and thoroughly, and then Biblion Deuteron and Triton -- you know what I've said is NOT a stretch.

To the contrary.

Couldn't be clearer.

Because this is the way these Men -- that is, Men like Plato and Heraclitus, and, for that matter, Xenophon -- a far less exalted thinker --

It's the way these Men, Men who lived in a Masculinist, Warrior Culture -- a Warriordom -- and whose ideas and ideals were shaped by a Warrior Kosmos, a Warrior World of Being -- thought.

It's the way they thought:

Manhood -- The First Notion of Goodness -- say Scott and Liddell ;

Manhood -- The Sum of All the Excellences of Man -- say Lewis and Short.

Those four Men were 19th-century classicists, highly regarded in their field, steeped in the books and the society they were studying, and still living in a predominately Masculinist and to a large degree Warrior -- Culture.

And that's how they defined Manhood -- Fighting -- and Fighting Manhood.

As The First Notion of Goodness ; and

The Sum of All the Excellences of Man.

And that understanding of Fighting Manhood as the First Notion of Goodness and the Sum of All the Excellences of Man -- is within the language and the way it's used.

Take, for example, this statement by Plato, in the Republic, regarding nude athletics:

[I]t is not long since the Greeks thought it disgraceful and ridiculous, as most of the barbarians do now, for men to be seen naked [gymnos]. And when the practice of athletics [gymnasion = nude athletics] began, first with the Cretans and then with the Lacedaemonians [Spartans], it was open to the wits of that time to make fun of these practices, don't you think so?

I do.

But when, I take it, experience showed that it is better [agathos] to strip [apoduo] than to veil all things of this sort, then the laughter of the eyes faded away before that which reason [logos] revealed to be best [aristos], and this made it plain that he talks idly who deems anything else ridiculous but evil [kakos], and who tries to raise a laugh by looking to any other pattern of absurdity than that of folly and wrong [kakia] or sets up any other standard of the beautiful [to kalon] as a mark for his seriousness than the good [to agathon].

~Plat. Rep. 5.452d, translated by Shorey.

So:
[I]t is not long since the Greeks thought it disgraceful and ridiculous, as most of the barbarians do now, for men to be seen naked. And when the practice of athletics [gymnasion = nude athletics] began, first with the Cretans and then with the Lacedaemonians [Spartans], it was open to the wits of that time to make fun of these practices, don't you think so?

But when, I take it, experience showed that it is better to strip than to veil all things of this sort

"it is better to strip than to veil all things of this sort"

That's unequivocal, isn't it?

The word Plato uses for "strip" is apoduo -- meaning strip off, strip naked, strip for the palaistra, etc. -- and it's quite common in ancient Greek literature.

Guys are constantly stripping, and with little provocation.

They just like taking off their clothes.

Because, clearly, to be "unclad" is to be Manly.

For example, when the reforming Spartan king Agis proposed restoring Sparta to her old way of austerity and equality, Plutarch tells us,

The younger men responded quickly, and more eagerly than he had expected: as a group they stripped to show their mettle, as if their clothes represented a way of life which they were all discarding in the cause of liberty.

They stripped to show their mettle -- their mettle, their Manliness.

It's a great phrase, and a great scene.

As is the moment when Alexander says to his assembled army, Come now, strip naked and show me your wounds, and I'll show you mine.

And you have to imagine Alexander stripping naked before his Men, and his Men stripping naked before him, so that all may show off their wounds, which are, as we discussed in Biblion Proton, Badges and Ikons -- Badges of Manliness, Ikons of Manhood.

Fighting Manhood.

And Plato, who preceded both Alexander and Agis, legitimates, in his philosophy, that already core Greek idea -- that Male Nudity is Manly, Manlier, Manliest -- by saying, "it's better to strip than to veil."

And the word Plato uses for "better" is the comparative of agathos, which is the adjectival form of the noun areté -- Manhood, manly excellence, manly goodness ; and that comparative form of the word can also mean not only stronger and braver -- but, most importantly, more Manly.

So what Plato is saying is that "it's better, it's stronger and braver, it's more excellent, it's more Manly, to strip than to veil all things of this sort."

It's more Manly -- to strip -- than to veil.

And then Plato says, "the laughter of the eyes faded away before that which reason revealed to be best"

And the word for best is Aristos -- which, like areté, derives from Ares:

αριστος Αρης

[aristos Ares]

~Liddell and Scott, 1889.

Look at it, guys, look at the definition's juxtaposition of the words Aristos and Ares, because it's just sitting there, that linkage between Aristos and Ares, between Best and Fight, between Most Manly and Fight -- it's just sitting there, plain for you and the rest of the world to see:

αριστος Αρης

Best derives from Fight, Aristos comes from Ares -- that's what Liddell and Scott are saying.

Just as -- and as we discussed in the Prolegomena, and in Biblion Proton *and* Biblion Deuteron:

Manhood is rooted in and flows from Fight, areté -- Manly Excellence -- is rooted in and flows from Ares -- the God of Fighting Manhood.

I wonder how many times I'd have to say it for you to believe it.

Too many, I expect, even though it's right there for you to see with your own eyes:

αριστος Αρης

αρετη Αρης

Those are links.

Click on the links and you'll see it:

αριστος Αρης

αρετη Αρης

But you won't.

You won't see it because you don't want to see it.

You're afraid to see it.

You're afraid.

Nevertheless, and despite your fear, which has continually, throughout your lives, and continues to, UN-man you -- Aristos means not only "best" but also "noblest" and "bravest" -- that is,

Most Manly.

So -- to the Greeks --

It's stronger and braver -- it's More Manly -- to strip -- than to veil.

And Reason reveals such Male Nudity to be Aristos -- not just Noblest and Bravest, but, most importantly, Most Manly.

Reason reveals Male Nudity -- in Fight Sport and in War -- to be Most Manly.

Male Nudity is Most Manly -- it is Manlier to be Nude -- than to be clad.

Which is why the MALE GODS, including ARES Himself, are usually depicted as NUDE MEN.

And what is it which tells us that Naked Truth and Nude Combat is stronger and braver and above all More Manly than the veils of opinion and lies?

REASON.

And Greek nouns have gender and Logos, as it happens, is Masculine.

Reason is Manly.

(See Sexual Freedom.)

Reason tells us, Reason reveals, what is Best:

[μηνυω = menuo = to disclose what is secret, reveal, betray, generally, to make known, declare, indicate]

"reason [logos] revealed to be best [aristos]"

Reason -- Manly Reason, Manly Rationality -- reveals that Male Nudity -- which is also Male Truth -- is Best -- Most Manly.

Manly Reason tells us -- Men -- what is most Manly.

And what is Most Manly?

To be a Man -- Fighting another Man -- Nude.

Plato:

and this made it plain that he talks idly who deems anything else ridiculous but evil,

Assholes -- the opinionated slackers of the world of becoming -- who can't think or reason, but can only talk -- "idly" -- those assholes will claim that male nudity is bad or silly or ridiculous.

But they're full of shit --

Only evil [kakia] is ridiculous.

and who tries to raise a laugh by looking to any other pattern of absurdity than that of folly and wrong or sets up any other standard of the beautiful [to kalon] as a mark for his seriousness than the good [to agathon].

So the only standard for the Beautiful -- To Kalon -- is the Good -- To Agathon.

Male Nudity -- particularly in Fight Sport because that's what Plato's talking about when he says gymnasion / nude athletics -- is both Beautiful -- Morally Beautiful -- and Good.

AND -- and it's an important "and" -- those who talk "idly" and "try to raise a laugh" about male nudity -- are supporting evil.

And the word Plato uses for evil is kakos -- which derives from kakke = shit.

While the word for Beautiful is Kalos = noble and beautiful.

And we're back to the Spartan Ta Kala -- The Noble Warrior Way of Manly Moral Beauty --

And Plato's word for Good is Agathos, which is the adjectival form of Areté -- Manhood, Manliness, Manly Excellence, Manly Goodness, Virtue.

So --

It's not long since the Greeks thought it disgraceful and ridiculous, as most of the barbarians do now, for men to be seen naked. And when the practice of nude male athletics began, first with the Cretans and then with the Spartans, it was open to the wits of that time to make fun of these practices.

But when experience showed that it's more manly to strip than to veil all things of this sort -- that is, the male genitals -- then the laughter of the eyes faded away before that which reason, which is itself manly, revealed to be most manly ;

and this made it plain that he talks idly who deems anything else ridiculous but evil, which of its nature is excremental, and who tries to raise a laugh by looking to any other pattern of absurdity than that of folly and wrong or sets up any other standard of the Morally and Manfully Beautiful as a mark for his seriousness than the Good -- which is Manhood.

That's what Plato is saying because that's what the words he uses -- mean.

Because it's what they reduce to by virtue -- of what they're rooted in:

Manliness and Manhood.

Which in turn are rooted in and flow from ARES -- the God of Fighting Manhood.

That's who Ares is.

Sokrates says so:

Ares, then, if you like, would be named for his virility [to arren] and courage [to andreion = courage, Manliness, Manhood], or for his hard and unbending nature, which is called arratos; so Ares would be in every way a fitting name for the God of War.

~Plat. Crat. 407d, translated by Fowler.

"Ares would be named for his Virility and Manhood, and for his Hard and Unbending, Muscular and Phallic, nature."

Virility and Manhood, Hard and Unbending, Muscular and Phallic.

Thus Sokrates.

Which is no doubt why the male genitals are displayed -- in combat:

It's better to strip than to veil -- because it's more Manly.

And Reason -- Logos -- which is itself Manly -- reveals -- that such stripping, such open display of the male genitals both in war and in what we today call "sport," but which is actually agonia -- one man's strenuous physical effort to overcome another -- is most Manly.

To say otherwise is to talk idly.

And it's wrong to do that.

It's wrong to set up any other standard of the Beautiful -- than the Good.

The Good -- which is Manhood, Fighting Manhood, originates in and devolves from Manly action, action taken in and during Combat.

The Beautiful is Moral Beauty -- and because the standard for the Beautiful is the Good -- Moral Beauty too must originate in and devolve from Manly action, action taken in and during Combat.

And in our discussion of Kalon and Ta Kala in Biblion Proton, I've given you examples of that.

Eg: Anaxibios, the Spartan commander, and his Lover, choosing to preserve eutaxia, good discipline, and die at their posts.

That's a Kalon -- a Morally Beautiful deed -- and its Moral Beauty derives from its relationship to the Good.

Such Good is called Manhood.

And it's the Supreme Good.

Which is why Liddell and Scott say that Manhood is the First Notion of Goodness ;

and Lewis and Short say that Manhood is the Sum of All the Excellences of Man.

And when they say Manhood -- they mean FIGHTING Manhood.





They mean Fighting.

So:

It's critical that you understand that both morally and spiritually and therefore "kosmically" -- that is, in terms of the Warrior Kosmos -- Fighting Manhood functions as and reduces to Fight ; and Fight functions as and reduces to Fighting Manhood.

Which we can see using two masterpieces of Greek art, works which you often see in my articles because they epitomize classicist Werner Jaeger's statement that such images express an "ideal unity of physical and spiritual which . . . indicates how we must understand the athletic ideal of manly prowess" -- that is, Fighting Manhood.

In other words, these works of art express an Ideal -- as in Warrior World of Being / Warrior Kosmos -- of Manly Prowess -- which is Manly Moral Order -- which is Fighting Manhood.









Further, and as I talked about in Biblion Triton, notice how essentially serene these depictions of Fighting Manhood and Fight itself -- actually are:

Their serenity devolves from their source -- which is the Warrior Kosmos, the Warrior World of Being, where all is timeless and changeless, immutable and eternal.

The Fight -- and Fighting Manhood -- are Forever.

And guys, it's important you understand this:

In the Warrior World of Being, in the Warrior Kosmos, these two Nude Men, these two Nude Warriors -- are Locked in Combat -- for all Eternity.

Their Fight NEVER ends.

So:

When you look at this art, what you're seeing is Fight -- and Fighting Manhood -- under its ETERNAL aspect.

You're being given a glimpse of Fight -- ManFight -- in Eternity:



Moreover:

If, Fighting Manhood = Fight and Fight = Fighting Manhood -- which they do --

Then Proten Aitian, Primal Cause, is identical to

  • Proton Philon : Primal Love.
[I]n Lysis, ... Plato coined the new concept of 'the Primal Love' (πρωτον φιλον -- proton philon), and maintained it was to be assumed as the source and origin of all friendship between Men. It is because of our general love for this ultimate object of desire that we love any individual. That is what we are trying to attain or realize in every kind of association with other Men, whatever its character may be. ... The other Socratic dialogues presuppose the Idea of Good [the Supreme Good, the Highest Good] as a fixed point of reference; and so too, in the discussion of the nature of friendship, it is assumed to be the absolute and final standard. For, although Plato does not say so expressly, the understanding reader will realize that 'the primal love', for whose sake we love all other things, implies the highest value, Good in itself.

















So -- and once again:

Because Fighting Manhood resides in the Warrior World of Being, the Warrior Kosmos, where it is, de facto, the Idea of Good, it's both the Primal Love and the Primal Cause of the Warrior All:

Of Brave Beauty -- kalokagathia ; and

Manly Moral Order ; and

All the other Excellences -- of Man:








So:

Fighting Manhood is the Sum and Father of All the Excellences of Man.

Corporeal, Mental, Moral, and Spiritual.

And those Corporeal, Mental, Moral, and Spiritual Excellences include --

Manly Moral Order -- which, as we'll eventually see, is essential to the well-being both of the Warrior himself -- and of his Warriordom.

Now:

I said that Fighting Manhood -- the Fight of Manhood Against Manhood -- ultimately resides in the Warrior World of Being -- the Warrior Kosmos.

Where the FIGHT -- is ETERNAL.

Where it's Man Against Man --

And Manhood Against Manhood --

Forever.

Fight Without End.

The Warrior Kosmos is the Warrior World of Being.

Eternal Fight -- Fight Without End -- exists -- it's REAL -- in the World of Being.

In the Word of Being, Two Men, Two Nude Men, Fight Each Other -- Man Against Man and Manhood Against Manhood -- FOREVER.

The Fighting we see in the World of Becoming -- is an approximation of that -- a copy of it.

Even so, seeing that Fighting makes Men -- "wild" -- that is, it frees them from the societally-dictated ways of opinion -- and returns them to their natural selves -- because witnessing the Fight super-charges Men erotically and that erotic energy then powers the way to communion with and knowledge of the Absolute Fighting Manhood of the Warrior Kosmos.

Classicist RG Bury on Being and Becoming:

In making this distinction, Plato was not innovating : long before him, [the philosopher] Parmenides had divided his exposition into two sections, "the Way of Truth," and "the Way of Opinion," while Democritus had drawn a sharp line of division between the "Dark Knowledge" we have of sensibles and the "Genuine Knowledge" which apprehends the only realities, the Atoms and the Void.

Both of those concepts really speak to me.

Fighting for me is the Way of Truth -- because it's the Way of Manliness.

That's why I use aphorisms in my work, aphorisms like The Way of the Warrior is the Way of Salvation ; and Manliness Equals Life.

Because -- for Men, Manliness does equal Life.

And because The Way of the Warrior is the Way of Salvation.

For Men.

For Men, Manliness and Manhood and Manly Spirit -- are Life.

And when Democritus says Genuine Knowledge is Knowledge of the Atoms --

what I think is that in a real Fight, the Men are Fighting on an atomic level.

Every atom of their being is engaged in the Fight.

Sweat, Blood, Skin, Bone, Muscle -- and Cum too.

We know that if two guys cum in the same cunt -- or just on each other's abs -- each Man's sperm will seek out the other's and try to destroy it.

Sperm will literally Fight Sperm.

In a Fight, on a macro level, it's Man Against Man.

On a micro level, it's atom against atom.

Sweat Against Sweat and Blood Against Blood.

Every Atom Against Every Other Atom.

Total, Pure, Unrelenting Manhood.

Sokrates says that Ares is Arratos -- Hard and Unyielding, Hard and Unbending, Hard and Unrelenting.

Unyielding, Unbending, Unrelenting Manhood.

Fighting Manhood.

Which is basic.

Foundational.

And goes to the heart of the Male Universe -- the Warrior Kosmos.

Fight -- Virtuous Struggle and Strife -- Fighting Manhood -- animates, is the Father of, All.

Including, reductionally, Manhood itself -- Manhood Man-ifested as Brave Beauty.







ΑΓΩΝ




MANHOOD: A LEXICON

BIBLION TETARTON
FIGHT IS THE FATHER OF ALL
Ares - Eros - Agon : Fighting Manhood and Manly Love

By Bill Weintraub

Now -- an important question:

If Fight is the Father of All -- which de facto means that Manhood -- Fighting Manhood -- is the Father of All -- can we reconcile that idea with Plato's statement that Eros is the origin of all spiritual effort?

As you'll see, the answer is -- Yes -- and easily.

But to understand that answer, we have to first understand the intellectual world into which Plato was born.

Here's Paul Shorey, in the UN-abridged edition of his magesterial book What Plato Said:

Plato is infinitely suggestive; his writings teem with ideas. But it is not the number of his ideas but his way of dealing with ideas that marks him as the world's first and greatest real philosopher. There was no lack of ideas in the society in to which Plato was born. The very air, as Pater says, was sickly with cast-off speculative atoms. He must have been early acquainted with Anaxagoras, who had been a conspicuous figure at Athens in the previous generation and whose doctrines Socrates in the Apology says can be bought from the orchestra for a drachma at the most, and one of whose books, according to a well-known passage of the Phaedo, was read aloud in Socrates' hearing in his youth. It would be a plausible assumption that he went on from Anaxagoras to Empedocles, Parmenides, and other Presocratics. He is said to have studied Heraclitus under Cratylus. The boy Lysis admits that he has met in writers about nature the great principle that like is friendly to like, and it is not probable that the boy Plato had less intellectual curiosity. Nearly all the Presocratics are discussed, mentioned, or alluded to somewhere in Plato's writings. The conjectural reconstruction of the systems of these thinkers occupies in recent literature a space disproportionate to our real knowledge of them. It is enough for our present purpose to note that Plato could find in them more than the germ of many ideas which are supposed to be distinctively modern.

He would find in nearly all of them the general conception of the reduction of this varied world to unity or to a few interchangeable elements. He would find not of course his own explicit antithesis between materialism and spiritualism, but the provocation and stimulus of it in a steadily progressive tendency to conceive true science as the mechanistic explanation of all things and the negation of all divine intervention. He would find also a conception of cycles of change, growth, and decay not differing appreciably for any practical purpose from Herbert Spencer's cycles of evolution and dissolution, or the fancy of the most recent popularizer of the new physics that the disintegration and resolution of matter into heat may save the universe from the death by "entropy" with which nineteenth-century physics threatened it. And he would find in Anaximander, whom he does not mention, and others a more or less serious poetic and allegorical interpretation of such philosophies in the fancy that individual existence is an injustice for which the individual must pay the penalty by reabsorption into the infinite and indeterminate. An idea which again for practical purposes does not differ appreciably from the reflections in Tennyson's ancient sage:

For all that laugh, and all that weep
And all that breathe, are one
Slight ripple on the boundless deep
That moves, and all is gone.

More specifically he would discover in Anaximander, Empedocles, and others, not of course the modern scientific doctrine of biological evolution, but its virtual equivalent for philosophical purposes, the hypothesis that life was somehow a spontaneous growth and that nature tried many experiments of which only the fitting survived, that the higher forms of life may have been outgrowths of the lower, that the prolonged infancy of man was a cause of the constitution of the family and so of the development of civilization; that the surface of the earth had been subject to vast changes in the long course of time.

Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the atomists, Leucippus, and Plato's own contemporary, Democritus, would familiarize his mind with hypotheses about the ultimate constitution of matter which though not based on the mathematics that support and complicate similar speculations today produce substantially the same impression on the lay mind even of a philosopher.

From Heraclitus and the Eleatics he would derive the antithesis so vividly described by Pater, and that pervades his own philosophy, between the experience of incessant change and the intellectual and moral necessity of the assumption of stability. In Heraclitus he would find the suggestion and the poetical or epigrammatic formulation of such extremely modern ideas as universal mutability, universal relativity, and yet a reign of law or reason somehow operating in and controlling the eternal process. In the Eleatics he would find the beginnings of that dialectic of being and not-being, the one and the many, the like and the unlike, which he himself in jest or in earnest was to push to the limit in anticipation of all verbal metaphysics from the neo-Platonists to the Scholastics and from the Schoolmen to Hegel and his successors.

[emphases mine]

What does Shorey tell us?

First of all, that the pre-Socratic Greek philosophers anticipated or just plain formulated first most of the scientific ideas we think of as "modern."

Translation:

Those ideas are not modern.

They originated in ancient Greece.

Then Shorey tells us that Plato "is said to have studied Heraclitus under Cratylus."

And indeed, Plato later wrote a dialogue titled the Cratylus.

Which discusses, among other things, the relationship between Ares and Manhood:

Ares, then, if you like, would be named for his virility [to arren] and courage [to andreion = courage, Manliness, Manhood], or for his hard and unbending nature, which is called arratos; so Ares would be in every way a fitting name for the God of War.

~Plat. Crat. 407d, translated by Fowler.

What you see there is that the name "Ares" -- because of its relationship to Arren -- Virility ; and Andreion -- Manhood ; and Arratos -- Hard and Unbending -- matters.

And that the name and idea of Ares -- that is, Ares as the personification of Manhood, Virility, Courage, Combat, and Fight -- like other hypostatized concepts -- provides *stability* -- in a world of constant change and flux.

Which Shorey in essence confirms -- and it's the crucial bit:

From Heraclitus . . . [Plato] would derive the antithesis that pervades his own philosophy, between the experience of incessant change and the intellectual and moral necessity of the assumption of stability.

In Heraclitus he would find the suggestion and the poetical or epigrammatic formulation of such extremely modern ideas as universal mutability, universal relativity, and yet a reign of law or reason somehow operating in and controlling the eternal process.

So -- from Heraclitus, and from his own deeply-held beliefs about the nature of the universe, beliefs which were supported by Sokrates, Plato determined that there is an "intellectual and moral necessity of the assumption of stability"; and "a reign of law or reason somehow operating in and controlling the eternal process."

That reign of law and reason exists, of course, in the World of Being -- which we explored in Biblion Deuteron -- Primal Love ;

and, for which World of Being, there is both an intellectual and moral necessity.

And we began to explore the intellectual necessity for the World of Being in Biblion Triton -- UN-forgetting.

Now:

It's clear, and both Jaeger and Shorey agree, that Plato got the notion of the World of Becoming from Heraclitus via Cratylus, and that of the World of Being from Sokrates.

According to Aristotle, says Jaeger,

As a young student, Plato attended the lectures of the Heraclitean Cratylus, who taught that everything flows and nothing has a permanent existence.

Then, when he met Socrates, a new world opened up to him. Socrates confined himself entirely to questions of morality, and tried to discover the eternal essence of the Just, the Beautiful, the Good, etc.

At first glance, the idea that everything changes, and the assumption that there is a permanent truth, seem to be mutually exclusive.

But Cratylus had so convinced Plato that everything changes, that his conviction could not be shaken even by the powerful impresssion he received from Socrates' determined search for a fixed point in the ethical world.

Plato therefore concluded that Cratylus and Socrates were both right, because they were speaking of two different worlds.

Cratylus' statement that everything flows referred to the only world he knew -- the world of sensible phenomena; and Plato continued even later to maintain that the doctrine of eternal change was true for the world of sense.

But Socrates, in the search for the conceptual essence of those predicates like 'good', 'just', 'beautiful', on which our existence as moral beings is based, was looking towards a different reality, which does not flow but truly 'is' -- because it remains immutably and eternally the same.

[emphasis mine]

So: The "conceptual essence of concepts like Good, Just, Beautiful" -- which reduce, as you've seen, to Manhood -- remains "immutably and eternally the same."

Key point: Our existence as Moral beings -- that is, as human beings -- must be based upon a reality which remains immutably and eternally the same.

Shorey agrees, but his analysis, as befits Shorey, is more complex:

From Heraclitus to John Stuart Mill human thought has always faced the alternative of positing an inexplicable and paradoxical noumenon,

  • Noumenon [ G. [German] fr. Gk [Greek] noumenon that which is apprehended by thought, fr. neut. of pres. past part. of noein to think, conceive, fr. nous mind ] (1798) : an object or concept which, according to Kant, can be known to exist but cannot be experienced and to which no properties can be intelligibly ascribed -- noumenal adj

    ~Merriam-Webster's Ninth Collegiate Dictionary, 1983

    In Kant, a phenomenon is an object of sense ; thus Plato's sensible realm becomes Kant's phenomenal, while the intelligible is the noumenal ; and --

    all power originates in the noumenal realm and flows to the phenomenal.

    That must be so, since the original forms, essences, ideas, etc must be more powerful than their copies.

Shorey:

From Heraclitus to John Stuart Mill human thought has always faced the alternative of positing an inexplicable and paradoxical noumenon, or accepting the "flowing philosophy [ie, all is in flux]." No system can escape the dilemma. Plato from his youth up was alternately fascinated and repelled by the philosophy of Heraclitus. No other writer has described so vividly as [Plato] the reign of relativity and change in the world of phenomena. Only by affirming a noumenon could he escape Heracliteanism as the ultimate account of (1) being, and (2) cognition. He chose or found this noumenon in the hypostatized concepts of the human mind, the objects of Socratic inquiry, the postulates of the logic he was trying to evolve from the muddle of contemporary dialectic, the realities of the world of thought so much more vivid to him than the world of sense. This is the account of the matter given by Aristotle and confirmed by the dialogues. Except in purely mythical passages, Plato does not attempt to describe the ideas any more than Kant describes the Ding-an-sich [thing in itself, the thing as such] or Spencer the "Unknowable." He does not tell us what they are, but that they are. And the difficulties, clearly recognized by Plato, which attach to the doctrine thus rightly limited, are precisely those that confront any philosophy that assumes an absolute.

[Shorey goes on to say that since Plato's time, philosophers, including Locke, Berkeley, JS Mill, and Taine, have worked out a partial solution to the problem.]

. . .

But the main issue is unaffected by this fact. Even if he had been acquainted with the analysis of Mill and Taine, Plato would have continued to ask : Are the good and the beautiful and similar essences something or nothing? Can everything in the idea be explained as the natural product of remembered and associated sensations? Is not man's power of abstraction something different in kind from any faculty possessed by the brute?

Not all the refinements of the new psychology can disguise the fact that the one alternative commits us to the "flowing philosophers," the other to some form of Platonism. For the answer that the "good" and the "beautiful" are only concepts of the mind is an evasion which commends itself to common-sense, but which will satisfy no serious thinker. If these concepts are the subjective correlates of objective realities, we return to the Platonic idea -- for Plato, it must be remembered, does not say what the ideas are, but only that they are in some sense objective and real.

[emphases mine]

~archive.org, The Unity of Plato's Thought

Plato "does not say what the ideas are, but only that they are in some sense objective and real."

In other words, they constitute a "noumenon" -- something you're sure exists, something you're certain is objective and real, but which you know can't be experienced, and to which attributes cannot be intelligibly ascribed.

You can, says Shorey, use myth in an attempt to describe the noumena, for, as Jaeger says,

Myth gives supposition the form and color needed by our mortal and finite imaginations.

For example, in the myth, Ares, God of War, fucks Aphrodite, Goddess of Sex.

And as you can see, His amorous efforts leave him, at least according to Botticelli, worn out.

And surrounded by young and playful satyrs, who, it would appear, seek to re-awaken Him -- to Love.

But His libidinous labors, and those of Aphrodite, will have been well worth the cost, for the child -- actually a youth -- which results from their coupling is Eros -- the God of Romantic Passion.

The myth gives the supposition -- that the union of War and Sex produces Manly Romantic Passion -- form and color.

Here's a Roman version:


Ares and Aphrodite at Pompeii

The depiction of Ares and Aphrodite is touching.

But Greek Eros has become infantilized -- he's now a Roman Cupid.

Nonetheless, you can, in this wall painting, plainly see how the myth gives supposition -- form and color.

So: you can use myth in attempting to describe the Ideas, Essences, and Forms.

And, I would say, you can use metaphor.

And you can certainly speak of your own, subjective, experience, as I have and NW has.

But:

It's *not* just subjective.

Because:

Here's what's at issue:

Are the good and the beautiful and similar essences something or nothing?

What do you you think?

Is Manhood -- something or nothing?

As we saw in Biblion Triton -- Book III -- if Manhood (or any other essence) is nothing but a passing thought -- changes in the world of becoming -- would and will wipe it out.

But if, we assume, it is "self-subsistent" -- self-existing -- independent of the world of becoming -- in a noumenon which Plato calls the World of Being -- it will exist forever, immutable and eternal.

And without that assumption, there's no satisfactory way to explain -- the human experience.

Shorey:

For the answer that the "good" and the "beautiful" are only concepts of the mind is an evasion which commends itself to common-sense, but which will satisfy no serious thinker. If these concepts are the subjective correlates of objective realities, we return to the Platonic idea -- for Plato, it must be remembered, does not say what the ideas are, but only that they are in some sense objective and real.

If the concepts in the human mind, concepts like Manhood, are "the subjective correlates of objective realities" --

That is, if a concept like Manhood in someone like NW's mind -- corresponds to an objective reality -- the Absolute Manhood in the World of Being -- Manhood exists, and NW's (and my own) accessing it as a child -- becomes explicable.

Shorey:

for Plato, it must be remembered, does not say what the ideas are, but only that they are in some sense objective and real

Why doesn't Plato say what the ideas are -- physically, that is?

Because, again, they're "noumena" -- objects and concepts which he and we know to exist, but which cannot be experienced, and to which no attributes -- such as height and weight -- can be "intelligibly" -- that is, reasonably -- ascribed.

So -- Plato and Bill Weintraub -- know that Absolute Fighting Manhood exists, as an Essence, a Form, an Idea, and an Ideal -- in the World of Being -- the noumenal realm.

But -- Plato and Bill Weintraub know that we can't experience that Idea -- in the sense of sensory experience -- for example, touch; nor can we reasonably give it attributes such as height and weight.

We can only say, based on our intellect, our reason, that it is in some sense objective and real.

And, that in my case, and that of NW, too, it informs everything we do.

Which makes it, functionally, and for both of us, the Idea of Good -- the Good Purpose in some Controlling Mind able to achieve that Purpose -- and the Sanction -- the Consideration, Principle, or Influence, which impels to Moral Action and determines Moral Judgment.

For, as Werner Jaeger says, paraphrasing Plato, "It is knowledge of the true standard which inevitably dictates our choice and determines our will."

It is knowledge -- gained in the World of Being -- of the true standard -- the Idea of Good, Fighting Manhood -- which inevitably dictates our choice and determines our will.

Now: Shorey emphasizes, in the passage we've just read, the conflict between Heraclitean flux and Platonic stability.

Nevertheless, it's important to remember, and Shorey also says, that Heraclitus, while stressing flux, also talks about the "truth" -- that is, Immutable and Eternal Truth -- that can be found in names -- that is, Ideas -- and thus suggests "a reign of law or reason somehow operating in and controlling the eternal process."

As in --



So: the important thing to understand is that Plato believed very strongly that there had to be stability, "a reign of law or reason operating in and controlling the eternal process."

That the Universe -- the Kosmos -- is not just about atoms colliding meaninglessly in the void -- but that the Kosmos has and must have -- a Moral Center.

Must.

And it's Plato who, among the Greeks, first uses the word Kosmos in the sense of "the world or universe, from its perfect order."

And for Plato, that Moral Center, that Moral Core, that Kosmic Moral Order -- resides in or is otherwise associated with -- the World of Ideas.


Now -- having, I hope, a better understanding of the intellectual milieu into which Plato was born and grew up -- and, more importantly, why he reasoned as he did -- let's get back to this question:

If Fight is the Father of All -- which de facto means that Manhood -- Fighting Manhood -- is the Father of All -- and remembering that both Manhood and Eros are Ideas, Forms, Essences, and Ideals in the World of Ideas -- that is, the World of Being -- how can we reconcile "Fight is the Father of All" -- with Plato's statement that "Eros is the origin of all spiritual effort?"

As you'll see, the answer is -- easily.

Fighting Manhood -- which is personified by the hypostatized Ares -- is the Father of All.

And Ares, as it happens, in Greek myth, is the Father of Eros -- Romantic Passion, particularly between Men.

That same Eros, you'll remember from the closing section of Biblion Proton, is an Agonist -- a Fighter.

He and his twin AntEros are Agonist and AntAgonist -- They Fight.

Not surprising, given that they're Sons of Ares -- the God of Fight and Fighting Manhood.


Eros and AntEros
Love is an Agon
Lovers are Agonists

Now, and please understand: Eros and AntEros are, for purposes of myth, and even, as we'll see, materialization, two beings ;

But -- together they constitute a Unit and a Unity, which we call, and which is -- EROS.

The God of Manly Romantic Passion.

How can that be?

Well, as Sallustius, a fourth-century AD Neo-Platonist and Hellenist says,

Myth represents the active operations [daimonia] of the Gods.

~Sallustius, Concerning the Gods and the Universe, translated by Nock.

And the Myth of Eros and AntEros represents how the Gods operate to actively bring about and sustain Love Between Men:

Agonistically.

Nevertheless, EROS Himself -- EROS as a Spiritual Force -- is a Unity:

The God of Manly Romantic Passion.

That same Eros, that same Manly Romantic Passion, which is a vast and immensely powerful spiritual force, in turn, says Plato, is the origin of all human spiritual effort.

Ares is the Father of All;

Ares is the Father of Eros; and,

Eros is the origin -- or Father, if you wish -- of all spiritual effort.

Not a problem.

Ares -- Fighting Manhood and the Struggle and Strife which that Manhood engenders -- is the Father of Eros -- Romantic Passion between Men.

Which in turn is an Agon.



And that Romantic Passion between Men -- is the Father of all spiritual effort -- the effort, in Plato's terms, to attain True Knowledge -- which is Knowledge of the Forms -- the Ideas, the Essences, the Ideals -- Eternal and Immutable -- in the World of Being.

Ares is the Father of Eros ;

Eros is the Father of Spirituality --

Spirituality which enables Men to access and understand -- Supreme and Absolute Manhood.

Question: what did Plato himself know about such Eros -- and the spiritual effort which it engendered?

Answer:

A lot.

First off, we have three epigrams that Plato wrote to two different Male "Beloveds."

The first two were to someone named "Aster," which means Star, and about whom we know nothing else, other than that he appears to have died.

Thou gazest on the stars, my star; ah, that I might be
Yon starry skies with thousand eyes that I might gaze on thee.

~translated by Shorey

Thou wert the morning star among the living
xxxEre thy fair life had fled.
Now having died thou art as Hesperus giving
xxxNew splendour to the dead.

~translated by Shelley

It was common for Male Lovers -- who were Warriors and who lived in Greek Warrior Culture -- to write these sorts of poems to their Male Beloveds.

Which I'm sure you all remember from our several discussions of Plato's Lysis.

For example, this one, in which a youth named Hippothales is in love with a youth named Lysis:

Says one of his Hippothales' friends:

Let me tell you, Sokrates, that our ears are numb from being hit with "Lysis this and Lysis that": and if Hippothales has had a bit to drink, we are apt to be roused from a deep sleep with the name "Lysis" ringing in our ears. And his talk about Lysis is bad enough, but he drowns us with poems and love letters. But worst of all is when we have to listen to him singing -- in his fine voice -- the praises of his boyfriend.

[A few moments later, Sokrates and his friend enter the palaistra and see Lysis in the apotuderion, or undressing room, with a group of other boys:]

... One of these was Lysis, who stood among the boys and young men wearing a garland on his head and had a distinct appearance, worthy to be called not just beautiful [kalos], but imbued with kalokagathia.

~translated by Miller

That last line of course is the one we usually see translated as "no less worthy of praise for his goodness than for his beauty."

That's how Male Lovers, in a Warrior Culture, a Warriordom informed by the Warrior Kosmos, thought of their Beloveds.

Not as sexual toys, but as Young Men imbued with both Goodness and Beauty.

Which is how Plato would have thought of his Beloved, Aster.

Where would he have met Aster?

Like Hippothales and Lysis, and Charmides and his friends, at the palaistra -- Wrestling, Boxing, etc -- and perhaps doing military training as well -- nude.

Before going to to the Third Epigram, which Plato wrote to Dion after Dion's death --

Let's talk about this one:

Thou wert the morning star among the living
xxxEre thy fair life had fled.
Now having died thou art as Hesperus giving
xxxNew splendour to the dead.

~translated by Shelley

What's interesting is that it was translated by the great English Romantic poet -- Percy Bysshe Shelley, who lived from 1792 to 1822.

Shelley, who was married to Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley -- the author of Frankenstein -- also, before the end of his short life, translated Plato's Symposion.

But he died before he could publish it.

Mary Shelley, who was extremely devoted to her husband and his memory, moved heaven and earth to get his translation published, saying in her preface to his Collected Works, published in 1839, that it was among the best things he'd ever done.

QUESTION:

Why was Mary Shelley not afraid, when she pushed to have her late husband's translation of Plato's great paean -- Παιαν -- hymn -- to Male-Male Love -- why was she not concerned that Shelley'd be accused, posthumously, of being a "homosexual," and she accused of having had a fraudulent marriage?

Why wasn't she worried about that?

After all, she, Shelley, and Lord Byron -- who was quietly known to be "bisexual" -- had spent a season together at Lake Geneva -- which is where she wrote Frankenstein.

Why -- given that potentially damning detail -- was Mary Shelley not concerned?

This is my email address:

Bill@Man2ManAlliance.org

Please write me with your answer, and please put Mary Shelley in the subject line.

I need to hear from at least one person -- not "Ann" -- prior to September 1 -- or I'm going to close the sites.

Because the answer is really, really, simple, and if, after fourteen years, not one of you knows it -- there's no point to keeping this site, which has turned into my own "Frankenstein," cobbled together from the ugly bits and ungainly pieces of the putative males who "visit" it -- going.

Now -- Plato wrote a third epigram -- there are thirty in all attributed to him, but only these three are thought to be authentic -- to his great Beloved, Dion, after Dion had been murdered in an attempt to free the city of Syracuse from tyranny.

I'm not going to tell you the story of Dion, and his relationship with Plato, and Plato's involvement in Dion's political struggles, because

  1. Plutarch's version, which is entertaining and informative, is easily available online; and

  2. You should have read that version at least a year ago, when I first mentioned it and linked to it in Sexual Freedom, which, once again, was posted more than a year ago.

So far as I can see, none of you have -- which is another reason to close the sites:

Not one of you has the good sense or even ability -- to tear yourself away from internet and cable tv trash, and spend perhaps thirty minutes reading about two authentic heroes -- Plato and Dion.

You know -- Men.

Real Men.

Who actually did something with their lives.

Anyways, here's Plato's classy epigram on the death of his Beloved, and beloved, -- Dion:

For Hecuba and Troy the fates had spun
xxxThe web of tears and sorrow from their birth;
For thee, O Dion, when the prize was won,
xxxThey spilt our cup of hope upon the earth.
A people mourns now where thou liest low,
Dion, whose love once set my soul aglow.

~translated by Shorey, What Plato Said, 1934

Plato was seventy-five when he wrote that.

Plato would have been about forty years old when he met, in 387 BC, Dion, who would have been about twenty, and who Plato always said was his best student.

And, clearly, he loved him.

This is Plato's description of that Love -- in his Symposion:

And if he meets, in conjunction with loveliness of form, a beautiful, generous, and gentle soul, he embraces both at once, and immediately undertakes to educate this object of his love, and is inspired with an overflowing persuasion to declare what is virtue [areté], and what he ought to be who would attain to its possession, and what are the duties which it exacts.

~Symposion 209B, translated by Shelley, 1818

Notice that Plato says the Lover embraces both and at once, the lovely form, and the beautiful, generous, and gentle soul.

From the Lysis forward, this thought is often given voice in the dialogues which discuss Eros, the God of Romantic Passion, of Manly Romantic Passion.

The passage continues:

For, by the intercourse with, and, as it were, the very touch of that which is beautiful, he brings forth and produces what he had formerly conceived [intellectually, spiritually, poetically -- that which is for the betterment of Mankind]; and nourishes and educates that which is produced together with the object of his love, whose image, whether absent or present, is never divided from his mind. So that those who are thus united are linked by a nobler community and a firmer love, as being the common parents of a lovelier and more enduring progeny than the parents of other [that is, human,] children. And everyone who considers what posterity Homer and Hesiod and the other great poets have left behind them, the sources of their own immortal memory and renown, or what children of his soul Lycurgus [the Spartan law-giver] has appointed to be the guardians, not just of Lacedaimon, but of all Greece; or what an illustrious progeny of laws Solon [the Athenian law-giver] has produced, and how many admirable achievements, both among the Greeks and Barbarians, men have left as the pledges of that love which subsisted between them and the beautiful, would choose to be the parent of such children than those in an human shape. For divine honours have often been rendered to them on account of such children, but on account of those in human shape, never.

~translated by Shelley

The idea that the "image [of the Beloved], whether absent or present, is never divided from [the Lover's] mind" is brought up again in Plato's Phaedrus, where the image [eikon] is described as AntEros.

Although in the Phaedrus, it's the Beloved who yearns for his Lover:

And when the other is beside him, he shares his respite from anguish, and when he is absent, he likewise shares his longing and being longed for, since he possesses a counter-love (anteros), which is the image of love (eros).

~Pl.Phdr.255d, translated by C W Wright.

Symposion:

"the image of the Beloved, whether absent or present, is never divided from the Lover's mind"

And Plato here identifies himself, and all who Love in his manner, with, appropriately in my view, Homer and Hesiod, Lycurgus and Solon, the great poets and law-givers of Greece, whose spiritual offspring have forever enriched the race of Men.

Now -- for those of you who find Shelley's translation difficult going, here's Jaeger's exposition of the passage:

He whose soul is full of the wish to beget looks for something beautiful by which to beget. If he finds a soul which is beautiful, noble, and talented, he greets the whole man, and makes many speeches to him about areté, and the character and pursuits which a good man should have, and he sets about educating him. So in contact and association with him, he begets the offspring he had within himself for so long. Both present and absent, he remembers his partner and shares with him in bringing to perfection that which he begot, so that their parentage is a far stronger link than any share in children begotten of the body, and their love is more lasting than that of marriage, because they share in more beautiful and more immortal children.

Homer and Hesiod [poets], Lycurgus [the Spartan lawgiver] and Solon [the Athenian lawgiver], are for Plato the highest Greek representatives of this Eros -- for through their works they have begotten all kinds of areté. Poets and legislators are alike in the educational force of their work. Plato regards the spiritual history of Greece from Homer and Lycurgus down to himself as a single unity. Poetry and philosophy, although he believes their conceptions of reality are widely and deeply separated, are united by the ideal of paideia [culture achieved through education], which springs from Eros, the love for areté.

Which is Manhood.

And of which Ares is the personification.

Eros is the Love of Manhood.

Eros is the Love of Ares.

Ares, who is the origin, the root, and the source, of all Areté.

αριστος Αρης

αρετη Αρης

Jaeger: for Plato, Lycurgus is one of "the highest Greek representatives of this Eros -- for through [his] works [he's] begotten all kinds of areté."

What sort of areté had Lycurgus begotten?

Answer: Virtue and Goodness in the form of Valour and Prowess in the service of the Spartan state.

Which is to say:

Manhood.

Fighting Manhood.

Spartan Fighting Manhood.

Whose acolytes were

the guardians, not just of Lakedaimon, but of all Greece

So:

The answer, then to my question -- What did Plato himself know about Eros -- and the spiritual effort which it engendered? --

Is -- a very great deal -- probably as much, if not more, than any other Man has ever known.

And if he meets, in conjunction with loveliness of form, a beautiful, generous, and gentle soul, he embraces both at once, and immediately undertakes to educate this object of his love, and is inspired with an overflowing persuasion to declare what is virtue [areté], and what he ought to be who would attain to its possession, and what are the duties which it exacts.


This Athenian grave stele or marker does not represent Plato and Dion,
but simply an older man and a younger, probably father and son.
Yet it could just as easily be Plato, in old age, contemplating the ghost, or his memories,
of the young, manly, acolyte of Virtue whom he'd met in Syracuse so many years before.
And if he meets, in conjunction with loveliness of form, a beautiful, generous, and gentle soul, he embraces both at once, and immediately undertakes to educate this object of his love, and is inspired with an overflowing persuasion to declare what is virtue [areté], and what he ought to be who would attain to its possession, and what are the duties which it exacts.

Virtue, of course, is Manhood.

Fighting, Moral, Manhood.

And the duty that Manhood exacted, in the case of Dion, was the overthrow of the tyranny which ruled his native city of Syracuse.

After many years of Struggle, Dion succeeded in ousting the tyrant.

But Dion was then murdered by an Athenian who'd claimed to be his friend.

Why did Dion seek to remove the tyrant?

Because Dion was Manly, Morally Beautiful, Worthy, Noble, and Virtuous -- that is, because he was a Man in full possession of his Manhood.

Aristotle, via Jaeger:

[it's] the highest kind of love which makes man reach out towards the highest areté [Manhood, Manly Excellence, Goodness, Virtue] through which he 'takes possession of the beautiful'.

The last phrase is so entirely Greek that it is hard to translate. For the Greeks, beauty meant nobility also. To lay claim to the beautiful, to take possession of it, means to overlook no opportunity of winning the prize of the highest areté.

Plutarch:

Though Dion was even before of a lofty character, magnanimous, and manly, he advanced still more in these high qualities when, by some divine good fortune, Plato came to Sicily.

This was not of man's devising, but some heavenly power, as it would seem, laying far in advance of the time a foundation for the liberty of Syracuse, and devising a subversion of tyranny, brought Plato from Italy to Syracuse and made Dion his disciple. Dion was then quite young, but of all the companions of Plato he was by far the quickest to learn and the readiest to answer the call of virtue, as Plato himself has written, and as events testify.

For though he had been reared in habits of submission under a tyrant, and though he was fully accustomed to a life that was subservient and timorous, as well as to ostentatious service at court and vulgar luxury and a regimen that counts pleasures and excesses as the highest good, nevertheless, as soon as he got a taste of a rational philosophy which led the way to virtue, his soul was speedily on fire; and since he very artlessly and impulsively expected, from his own ready obedience to the call of higher things, that the same arguments would have a like persuasive force with Dionysius, he earnestly set to work and at last brought it to pass that the tyrant, in a leisure hour, should meet Plato and hear him discourse.

At this meeting the general subject was human virtue, and most of the discussion turned upon manliness. And when Plato set forth that tyrants least of all men had this quality, and then, treating of justice, maintained that the life of the just was blessed, while that of the unjust was wretched, the tyrant, as if convicted by his arguments, would not listen to them, and was vexed with the audience because they admired the speaker and were charmed by his utterances.

[emphases mine]

Plut. Dio 5.1, translated by Perrin

Dion succeeded in removing the tyrant, but then was treacherously and traitorously killed.

Sad for Plato.

But Dion had done what was morally right and necessary, he had taken possession of 'the beautiful,' of kalon, Moral Beauty -- Brave Beauty -- and thus fulfilled his Destiny -- as a Man.

And Dion's murderer?

[H]e at once lost Syracuse, [and] being in straitened circumstances and unable to support his mercenaries properly, he was put to death by Leptines and Polyperchon, who, as fortune would have it, used the shortsword with which Dion also was said to have been smitten. And it was known by its size, which was short, after the Spartan fashion, and by the style of its workmanship, being delicately and cunningly wrought.


So -- I've said and we've seen that

ΑΓΩΝ

And in the Warrior Kosmos of ancient Greece, as in our own, the Struggle for Manhood, the Agonia of Brave Beauty Against Brave Beauty -- is what elicits, what brings forth, Eros --

the origin of all spiritual effort.

In ancient Greece, after all, the palaistrai / gymnasia, as well as the Games, the Agones, which were the product of the palaistrai / gymnasia, were the loci of male-male courtship and male-male romance.

Passionate Romance.

Romantic Passion.

Eros.

Remember the story of Autolycus, the Manly Youth who was Loved by Callias because of his Victory in Pankration.

Autolycus, says Sokrates, is possessed of "physical strength and stamina, virile courage -- that is, andreia, which is Fighting Manhood -- and sophrosyne -- self control."

Classicist Werner Jaeger:

It is, after all, easy to understand how a passionate admiration of noble bodies and balanced souls could spring up in a race which for countless years had prized physical prowess and spiritual harmony as the highest good attainable by man, and which had striven by grave and ceaseless rivalry, by exertion involving the utmost energies of mind and body alike, to bring those qualities to the greatest possible perfection.

Men who loved the possessors of those enviable qualities were moved by an ideal, the love for areté. Lovers who were bound by the male Eros were guarded by a deeper sense of honour from committing any base action, and were driven by a nobler impulse in attempting any honourable deed.

The Spartan state deliberately made Eros [Male-Male Love] a factor, and an important factor, in its agogé.













So:

In the Warrior Kosmos, and as the ancient myth tells us, Ares is the Father of Eros.

No question of that.

Again, Ares is the Father of Eros.

Fight is the Father of Romantic Passion -- between Men.

Which means that effectively, and not surprisingly, Fighting Manhood -- is the Father of All that's most significant -- in the Warrior Kosmos:

Manly Aggression; and,

Manly Love.

Which sexually, in the form of Phallus Against Phallus, can be characterized as Combative and Aggressive:

Aggressive Affection and Affectionate Aggression.

Combative Phallic Love and Loving Phallic Combat.



Some of you have a problem with those formulations.

Why?

In Hyacinthine Love, which was published fourteen years ago, I speak of "a hard, combative love in which our cocks would strive to prove who was master. . ."

While NW and Stan, the two wrestlers who we discussed in Biblion Triton, obviously felt affection for each other -- affection and more.

Yet they were also aggressive with each other.

Which means -- and which Men have known for millenia -- that it's possible to experience both aggression and affection -- with the same person -- simultaneously.


Letter from NW:

Once at college, where I was on the wrestling team, I was working out at the weight room. Near me was a really cute redhead whom I noticed had been working out every day at the same time that I did. We probably had similar schedules.

I also used to see him naked with me in the huge gang shower room. He had a natural lean, defined body of a guy who worked out. Naked in the showers, I could not help observe the Celtic Orange Bush and his beautiful Celtic translucent genitals. I can still picture him today. Just enough muscle to fight, no excess.

He was also in the P.E. Boxing class offered at the college then. I used to watch him work out on the bag, with his shirt off. All the guys boxed shirtless, just like the wrestlers went shirtless. The boxing room had huge windows and it was possible to watch the sparring and punching bag work by the young guys in the men's boxing class. I was never comfortable with the idea of boxing -- back then. It was never in my comfort zone to box, until I went to MMA / Fight School a couple of decades later. Boxing is serious stuff. It requires concentration. It requires courage. And it requires a willingness to get hit.

AND . . . it requires an atmosphere of comfort and expectation of boxing as Normal. Boxing requires boys to be in a structure growing up that says that fighting is, at the very least, OK.

That was NOT the message I had growing up. The message I got about boxing, growing up, was that it was low class, and below me, and not something that I should even watch -- in spite of the fact that secretly watching it on TV as a boy was totally infatuating to me. And in that boxing class, and in that weight room, here was this cut redheaded amateur boxing boy doing weights and ending up in the shower room with me almost every day.

Well, partaking of boxing was something that did not happen to me for two decades after college.

I wish I had taken the two boxing classes they offered back then.

In retrospect I realize, he must have noticed me too. I was just oblivious to it, being in the forced heterosexualized world I was in, even in the 1980s.

One day, I was sitting on a weight bench in that weight room, very few people around. He came up to me, tapped me on the shoulder and asked me to spot him on the bench press . . . That was a signal of interest and I just did not know it then. I said sure and went over to the bench press.

As I lifted and held the bar for him, I looked down into his blue eyes, and reddish eye brows. My package was directly over his face.

All that went through my mind was: I can't be "gay" no matter what.

The sheer stupidity of "gay."

I have relived that moment, of him looking up at my crotch as I stood over him holding the bar, at least a million times in my mind. I was so terrified of my own attraction to him (the attraction to the manliness in him, as a guy doing weights, as a guy who put the gloves on in a P.E. class and actually boxed/hit to the face and got hit) that I never bothered to switch out with him and do a few sets myself. I think I spotted him 3 times.

He never asked me after that.

I remember shaking hands with him and exchanging names. And that was it.

I saw him in the weight room for the rest of that year and I saw him in the shower room, naked and built to fight, periodically for the rest of that year. I would avoid the showers if he was in there, for the simple reason that the dude made my cock get hard.

Several times, I saw him strip naked at his locker, turn to glance at me, take his time to give me time to get naked also. He would walk toward the showers, glancing over his shoulder at me. It was an invite. I was terrified to take the bait.

He was beautiful. And he was manly. And he boxed. I wanted to be with that dude.

I wanted to box him naked, even though I could not box then.

The fighter in him was like a magnet. It made my cock get hard to think of him, let alone be near him.

I wanted cock2cock with that orange-haired, beautiful pink cock and ball sack. I can still shoot a load thinking about him.

In 25 years I've never seen the guy, but I have always thought of him.

It MUST be something spiritual. It is a very powerful feeling.

Imagine boxing, cock2cock. Just imagine it.

What a thing to partake of.


This concludes the first three sections of Biblion Tetarton -- Book IV -- of Manhood: A Lexicon.

Click here to access the last two sections of Biblion Tetarton:

Click here to go back to the Biblion Tetarton List of Contents.

Bill Weintraub

July 20, 2013








© All material Copyright 2018 by Bill Weintraub. All rights reserved.





Click here to go Back
to
Contents.

Click here to go Forward
to the concluding two sections of









who reject anal penetration, promiscuity, and effeminacy
among men who have sex with men

and













Manhood: A Lexicon

is presented by

The Man2Man Alliance

an Alliance of Men into Frot ;

and by

Ares is Lord

a Holy Communion of Men
Who Celebrate, Exalt, and Worship
Fighting Manhood
In the Divine and Sacred Person of
L o r dxA r e s,
The Warrior God
God of Fight, God of Manhood, God of Fighting Manhood


The Man2Man Alliance

Heroic Man2Man

Heroes

Frot Club

Personal Stories

| What's Hot About Frot | Hyacinthine Love | THE FIGHT | Kevin! | Cockrub Warriors of Mars | The Avenger | Antagony | TUFF GUYZ | Musings of a BGM into Frot | Warriors Speak | Ask Sensei Patrick | Warrior Fiction | Frot: The Next Sexual Revolution | Sex Between Men: An Activity, Not A Condition |
| Heroes Site Guide | Toward a New Concept of M2M | What Sex Is | In Search of an Heroic Friend | Masculinity and Spirit |
| Jocks and Cocks | Gilgamesh | The Greeks | Hoplites! | The Warrior Bond | Nude Combat | Phallic, Masculine, Heroic | Reading |
| Heroic Homosex Home | Cockrub Warriors Home | Heroes Home | Story of Bill and Brett Home | Frot Club Home |
| Definitions | FAQs | Join Us | Contact Us | Tell Your Story |

© All material on this site Copyright 2001 - 2018 by Bill Weintraub. All rights reserved.










It was my own innate understanding of the essentially Combative and Aggressive nature of Men, and my own instinctual relating of that to the testicles, which produced those fantasies and gave them so much power in my life.




































In this Dialogue, written in the first century AD by Lucian but presenting an imagined conversation between the *sixth century BC* Athenian lawgiver Solon and a Scythian visitor to Athens named Anacharsis, we get some idea of what that training was like -- starting with Athenian kids, and then progressing to Spartan youth:

Anacharsis: And another thing, my dear Solon, why are those young men acting in this way? Look, some of them are grappling and tripping each other, others are choking their friends and twisting their limbs, rolling about in the mud and wallowing like pigs. But before they began to do this, I noticed they first took off their clothes, then put oil on themselves, and in a peaceful fashion took turns in rubbing each other. But now, experiencing some emotion I do not understand, they have lowered their heads and are crashing into each other, and butting their heads together like rams! And look! There is one who has just seized the other by the legs and thrown him down; then he flopped on him and did not allow him to get up, but shoved him down into the mud. And now he is finally twisting his legs around the other person's waist and choking him with his arm under his throat. The other is slapping him on the shoulder, trying to ask him, I suppose, not to choke him to death. They do not avoid getting covered with dirt even to save the oil, but on the contrary wipe it off, and smearing themselves with mud and rivers of perspiration they make themselves ridiculous, in my opinion, by sliding in and out of each other's hands like eels.

Others are acting in the same way in the open part of the courtyard. However, these are not in the mud, but they have this deep sand in the pit which they sprinkle on themselves and each other, just like roosters, so that they cannot break out of their grasp, I imagine, since the sand decreases the slipperiness and offers a surer grip on a dry skin.

Others also covered with dust are standing up straight and striking and kicking each other. See that one there! Poor fellow, he seems to be ready to spit out a mouthful of teeth considering how full of blood and sand his mouth is; he has got a blow to the jaw, as you can see for yourself. But the official there does not separate them and stop the fight -- at least I assume he is an official from his scarlet cloak. On the contrary he encourages them and cheers the one who struck that blow.

All around different people are all exercising: some raise their knees as if running, although they remain in the same place, and as they jump up they kick the air.

What I want to know is, what reason do they have for doing this? It seems to me these actions are almost insane, and there is no one who can easily persuade me that people who act like this have not lost all their senses.

[Solon explains that customs differ from one land to another. He then explains to Anacharsis what is happening.]

Solon: This place, dear Anacharsis, is what we call a gymnasion and it and is sacred to Lykeian Apollo. You can see his statue, leaning against a stele, holding his bow in his left hand. His right arm is bent above his head as if the artist were showing the God resting, as if he had completed some laborious task. As for those exercises in the nude, the one done in the mud is called wrestling. Those in the dust are also wrestling. Those who strike each other standing upright we call pankratiasts. We have other athletic events: we have contests in boxing, diskos, and the long jump, and the winner is considered superior to his fellows and takes the prize.

Anacharsis: These prizes of yours now; what are they?

Solon: At Olympia there is a crown of wild olive; at Isthmia, one of pine; at Nemea, one woven of celery; at the Pythian Games, laurel berries sacred to the god, and here at home at the Panathenaic Games, oil from olive trees which grow in the sacred precincts. What are you laughing at, Anacharsis? Do these prizes seem valueless to you?

[Solon explains the symbolic value of the prizes, justifies the pursuit of athletics, the education of the citizens. Then Anacharsis asks Solon to explain the government of Athens.]

Solon: It is not easy, my friend, to explain everything at once in concise form, but if you will take one thing at a time you will learn everything about our belief in the gods, as well as our attitude toward parents, marriage, or anything else.

I will now explain our theory about young men and how we treat them from the time when they begin to know the difference between right and wrong and are entering manhood and sustaining hardships, so that you may learn why we require them to undergo these exercises and force them to subject their bodies to toil, not just because of the athletic games and the prizes they may win there, for few of them have the ability to do that, but so that they may try to gain a greater good for the entire city and for themselves. For there is another contest set up for all good citizens and the crown is not made of pine nor of wild olive nor of celery, but is one which includes all of man's happiness, that is to say, freedom for each person individually and for the state in general: wealth, glory, pleasure in our traditional feast days, having the entire family safe from harm, and in a word, to have the best of all the blessings one could have from the gods.

All this happiness is woven into the crown to which I referred and is acquired in the contest to which these exhausting exercises lead.

[Solon goes into more detail about the training of young men and about the responsibility of the citizens.]

Solon: As for physical training, which you particularly wanted to hear about, we proceed as follows. When the boys reach an age when they are no longer soft and uncoordinated, we strip them naked. We do this because first, we think they should get used to the weather, learning to live with different seasons, so they are not bothered by the heat nor do they yield to the cold. Then we massage them with olive oil and condition the skin. For since we see that leather which is softened by olive oil does not easily crack and is much stronger, even though it is not alive, why should we not think that live bodies would benefit from oil? Next we have thought up different kinds of athletics and have appointed coaches for each type. We teach one how to box, another how to compete in the pankration, so that they can become used to hard work, to stand up to blows face to face, and not to yield through fear of injury.

This creates two valuable traits in our young men: it makes them brave in the face of danger and unsparing of their bodies, and it also makes them strong and vigorous. Those who wrestle and push against each other learn how to fall safely and spring up nimbly, to endure pushing, grappling, twisting, and choking, and to be able to lift their opponent off the ground. They are not learning useless skills but they get the one thing which is the first and most important thing in life: through this training their bodies become stronger and capable of enduring pain. There is another thing too which is not unimportant. From this training they acquire skills which they may need some day in war. For it is clear that if a man so trained grapples with an enemy, he will trip and throw him more quickly and if he is thrown he will know how to regain his feet as easily as possible. For we prepare our men, Anacharsis, for the supreme contest, war, and we expect to have much better soldiers out of young men who have had this training, that is, the previous conditioning and training of naked bodies, which makes them not only stronger and healthier, more agile and fit, but also causes them to outweigh their opponents.

You can see, I should think, the results of this, what they are like when armed, or even without weapons how they would strike terror in their enemies. Our troops are not fat, pale, and useless nor are they white and scrawny ... enervated by lying in the shade, simultaneously shivering and streaming with rivers of sweat, gasping beneath their helmets, particularly if the sun, as now, is burning with noontime heat. What use could people be who get thirsty and cannot endure dust; soldiers who panic if they see blood, who die of terror before they come close enough to throw their spears or to close with the enemy? But our troops have skin of high color, darkened by the sun, and faces like real men; they display great vigor, fire, and virility. They glow with good health, and are neither shriveled skeletons nor excessively heavy, but they have been carved to perfect symmetry; they have used up and sweated off useless and excess flesh, and that which is left is strong, supple, and free, and they vigorously keep this healthy condition. For just as the winnowers do with wheat, so our athletes do with their bodies, removing the chaff and the husks and leaving the grain in a clean pile.

Through training like this a man can't avoid being healthy and can stand up indefinitely under stress. Such a man would sweat only after some time, and he would seldom be seen to be ill. Suppose someone were to take two torches and throw one into the grain and the other into the straw and chaff -- you see, I am returning to the figure of the winnower. The straw, I think, would burst into flames much more quickly, but the grain would burn slowly with no large flames blazing up nor would it burn all at once, but it would smoulder slowly and eventually it too would be burned.

Neither disease nor fatigue could easily attack and overcome such a body or easily defeat it. For it has good inner resources which defend it against attacks from outside, so as not to let them in, neither does it admit the sun or the cold to its hurt. To avoid yielding to hardships, great vigor springs up within, something prepared long in advance and held in reserve for time of need. This vigor fills up at once and waters the body in a crisis and makes it strong for a long time. For the previous training in bearing strain and hardship does not weaken their strength but increases it, and when you fan it the fire burns stronger.

We train them to run, getting them to endure long distances as well as speeding them up for swiftness in the sprints. This running is not done on a firm springy surface but in deep sand, where it is not easy to place one's foot forcefully and not to push off from it, since the foot slips against the yielding sand. We train them to jump over ditches, if they have to, or any other obstacles, and in addition we train them to do this even when they carry lead weights as large as they can hold. They also compete in the javelin throw for distance. In the gymnasium you also saw another athletic implement, bronze, circular, like a tiny shield with no bar or straps. You handled it as it lay there and expressed the view that it was heavy and hard to hold on to because it was so smooth. Well, they throw this up in the air both high and out, competing to see who can throw the longest and pass beyond the others. This exercise strengthens the shoulders and builds up the arms and legs.

As for this mud and dust, which originally seemed so amusing to you, my friend, listen while I tell you why it is used. First, their fall will not be on unyielding dirt but they will fall safely on soft ground. Next, their slipperiness has to be greater when they sweat in the mud. You likened them to eels, but the facts are neither useless nor humorous: it adds not a little to strength of the sinews when they are forced to hold firmly to people in this condition when they are trying to slip away. Do not think it is easy to pick up a sweaty man in the mud, covered with oil and trying to get out of your arms. All these skills, as I said earlier, are useful in combat, if it were necessary to pick up a wounded friend and carry him easily to safety or to seize an enemy and bring him back in your arms. And for this reason we train them beyond what is necessary, so that when they have practiced hard tasks they may do smaller ones with much greater facility.

We believe the dust is used for the opposite reason than the oil is, that is, so that a competitor may not slip out of his opponent's grasp. For after they have been trained in the mud to hold fast to something which is escaping from them because of its slipperiness, they then practice escaping out of the arms of their opponent, no matter how impossibly firm they may be held. Furthermore when this dust is used liberally it checks the perspiration and makes their strength last longer and furnishes protection against harm from drafts which otherwise attack the body when the pores are open. Besides, the dust rubs off the accumulation of dirt and makes the skin gleam.

I should dearly like to stand one of those white-skinned fellows who live in the shade beside one of our boys who work out in the Lykeion, and after I had washed off the dust and the mud, ask you which one you would like to resemble. For I know that you would choose at first glance, without hesitation, even without putting either through any tests, the one which is solid and hard rather than soft, weak, and pale, because what little blood he has has been withdrawn into the interior of his body.

[Anacharsis then ridicules the idea that athletic training could be useful in war. Why not save your strength, he asks. Solon explains that strength cannot be saved like a bottle of wine; it must be constantly used.]

Anacharsis: I just don't understand what you said, Solon. It is too intellectual for me and requires a sharp mind and keen insight. But above all, tell me this, why, in the Olympic Games and at Isthmia and Delphi and elsewhere, where so many competitors, you say, assemble to see these young men compete, you never have a contest with weapons but you bring them before the spectators all naked and exhibit them getting kicked and punched, and then, if they have won, give them berries and wild olives? It would be worth knowing why you do this.

Solon: My dear Anacharsis, we do this because we think that their enthusiasm for athletics will increase if they see that those who excel at them are honored and are presented to crowds of Greeks by heralds. Because they are to appear stripped before so many people, they try to get into good condition, so that when they are naked they will not be ashamed, and each one works to make himself capable of winning. As for the prizes, as I said earlier, they are not insignificant: to be praised by the spectators, to be a recognized celebrity, and to be pointed out as the best of one's group. As a result of these prizes, many of the spectators who are of the right age for competition go away completely in love with courage and struggle. If someone should remove love of glory from our lives, what good would we ever achieve, Anacharsis, or who would strive to accomplish some shining deed? But now it is possible for you to imagine from these games what sort of men these would be under arms, fighting for fatherland and children and wives and temples, when they show so much desire for victory in competing for laurel berries and wild olives.

Furthermore, how would you feel if you should observe fights between quails and between roosters here among us, and see the great interest which is shown in them? Wouldn't you laugh, particularly if you should learn that we do this in accordance with our laws and all men of military age are instructed to be present and to see these birds fight until they are exhausted? But it is no laughing matter, for eagerness for danger creeps insensibly into their souls so that they try not to seem less courageous and bold than the roosters nor to give in too soon because of injury or fatigue or any other distress.

As for trying them in armed combat and seeing them receive wounds -- never! It is brutal and dreadfully wrong, and in addition it is economically unfeasible to destroy the bravest, whom we could better use against our enemies.

Since you tell me, Anacharsis, that you expect to travel to the rest of Greece, if you get to Sparta, remember not to laugh at them nor think that they have no purpose when they compete in a theater, rushing together and striking each other, fighting over a ball, or when they go into a place surrounded by water [known as Plantanistas, or Plane-Tree Grove], choose up sides, and fight as if in actual war, although as naked as we Athenians are, until one team drives the other out of the enclosure into the water, the Sons of Herakles beating the Sons of Lykurgos or vice versa; after this contest there is peace and no one would strike another.

~ translated by Sweet.























The great Greek philosophers Sokrates and Plato spent a lot of time debating and defeating the hedonists of their day.

Plato wrote three very powerful books detailing that debate, beginning with the Protagoras, continuing in the Gorgias, and culminating in the Republic, one of the most important works of Western literature.

In the Gorgias in particular, Sokrates identifies hedonism with those who in his day, engaged in anal.

And since anal was proscribed -- forbidden -- by the Greeks, he uses that fact to defeat the hedonists.

Here's the debate -- the hot-headed hedonist is a guy named Callicles, and he's debating Sokrates:

Socrates. Come now, let me tell you another parable:

Consider if each of the two lives, the temperate and the licentious, might be described by imagining that each of the two men had a number of jars; the one man has his jars sound and full, one of wine, another of honey, and a third of milk, besides others filled with other things, and the sources which fill them are scanty and difficult, and he can only obtain them with a great deal of hard toil. Well, one man, when he has taken his fill, neither draws any more nor troubles himself a jot, but remains at ease on that score. The other, in like manner, can procure sources, though not without difficulty; but his vessels are leaky and unsound, and night and day he is compelled to fill them constantly, and if he pauses for a moment, he is in an agony of extreme distress. If such is the nature of each of the two lives, do you say that the licentious man has a happier one than the orderly? Do I not convince you that the opposite is the truth?

Callicles. You do not convince me, Socrates, for the one who has filled himself has no longer any pleasure left; and this, as I was just now saying, is the life of a stone: he has neither joy nor sorrow after he is once filled; but a pleasant life consists rather in the largest possible amount of inflow.

Soc. Well then, if the the inflow be large, must not that which runs away be of large amount also, and the holes for such outflow be of great size?

Cal. Certainly.

Soc. The life which you are now depicting is not that of a dead man, or of a stone, but of a plover [a bird thought to drink and then to eject the liquid]; you mean that he is to be hungering and eating?

Cal. Yes.

Soc. And he is to be thirsting and drinking?

Cal. Yes, that is what I mean; he is to have all his desires about him, and to be able to live happily in the gratification of them.

Soc. Capital, excellent; go on as you have begun, and have no shame; I, too, must disencumber myself of shame: and first, will you tell me whether you include itching and scratching, provided you have enough of them and pass your life in scratching, in your notion of happiness?

Cal. What a strange being you are, Socrates! a regular stump-orator.

Soc. That was the reason, Callicles, why I scared Polus and Gorgias, until they were too modest to say what they thought; but you will not be too modest and will not be scared, for you are such a manly fellow. And now, answer my question.

Cal. I answer, that even the scratcher would live pleasantly.

Soc. And if pleasantly, then also happily?

Cal. To be sure.

Soc. But what if the itching is not confined to the head? Shall I pursue the question? And here, Callicles, I would have you consider how you would reply if consequences are pressed upon you, especially if in the last resort you are asked, whether the life of a catamite is not terrible, shameful, and wretched? Or would you venture to say, that they too are happy, if they only get enough of what they want?

Cal. Are you not ashamed, Socrates, of introducing such topics into the argument?

Soc. Well, my fine friend, but am I the introducer of these topics, or he who says without any qualification that all who feel pleasure in whatever manner are happy, and who admits of no distinction between good and bad pleasures? And I would still ask, whether you say that pleasure and good are the same, or whether there is some pleasure which is not a good?

~translated by Jowett and Lamb

So: Socrates asks, "Is there some pleasure which is not a good?"

And the word "catamite" in the original Greek is kinaidos, that is, one who is anally passive, and/or who participates in anal penetration.

That is, an analist.

"Is there some pleasure which is not a good?"

Anal.

The life of an analist, says Sokrates, is "terrible, shameful, and wretched."

And Callicles doesn't dare disagree with him.

Because the cultural prohibition against anal is too severe.

I have no question that privately, Callicles thinks anal is okay.

That to his mind, "If it feels 'good,' do it!" and "It's all sex and it's all good!" -- are imperatives.

But he doesn't dare say so -- regarding anal.

Because again, the cultural prohibition against anal is too severe.

As it should be.










Recently I've been reading John Milton, the great English poet and defender of the Puritan and Parliamentary Revolution. I've been reading his prose pieces -- which were written to advance that Revolutionary cause. If you think I'm dogmatic and militant -- you should read Milton. But his militancy helped bring about the freedoms we have today.

As Warrior Brian said to me in an email regarding the need to organize:

If an army went into battle without proper training and organisation they would lose. Historic example, in the English Civil War (1642 to 1646) the army of King Charles 1st was better organised and won most of the first battles; however Oliver Cromwell trained and organised the men fighting on Parliament's side into the New Model Army, and they won! If they had not been so organised the King would have carried on as the dictator he had been. Maybe eventually we would have got the freedoms that we enjoy now but it would have come more slowly and the monarch would have given them very grudgingly; so organisation is as you say vital to winning.

And Militancy is vital -- to organization.












Please note:

This is not the Lexicon.

This is just a list of words.

If all you do is glance at this list, without reading the Lexicon itself, you

a.) Will not learn or otherwise benefit from either the Lexicon or this list; and

b.) Will betray yourself to me if you write to me -- because I know when someone's done the reading -- or hasn't.

Put differently:

The Lexicon spells out and otherwise makes plain the relationship between and among these words.

The list doesn't.

It's just a list.

Translation:

There is a HUGE difference between this list -- and the Lexicon.

So -- if you want to stay abreast with the Alliance, and understand why the Alliance thinks and acts as it does --

And what that means for your one sweet and precious life --

You need to read the Lexicon.

Bill Weintraub


MANHOOD: A LEXICON
Word List

Ancient Greek Words:

Modern English Words



Manhood: A Lexicon

is presented by

The Man2Man Alliance

an Alliance of Men into Frot ;

and by

Ares is Lord

a Holy Communion of Men
Who Celebrate, Exalt, and Worship
Fighting Manhood
In the Divine and Sacred Person of
L o r dxA r e s,
The Warrior God
God of Fight, God of Manhood, God of Fighting Manhood

© All material Copyright 2018 by Bill Weintraub. All rights reserved.


Theodorus
It is not easy, Socrates, for anyone to sit beside you and not be forced to give an account of himself and it was foolish of me just now to say you would excuse me and would not oblige me, as the Lacedaemonians do, to strip [apoduo]; you seem to me to take rather after Sciron. For the Lacedaemonians tell people to go away or else strip, but you seem to me to play rather the role of Antaeus; for you do not let anyone go who approaches you until you have forced him to strip and wrestle [prospalaio προσπαλαιω] with you in argument.

Socrates
Your comparison with Sciron and Antaeus pictures my complaint admirably; only I am a more stubborn combatant than they; for many a Heracles and many a Theseus, strong men of words, have fallen in with me and belabored me mightily, but still I do not desist, such a terrible love of this kind of exercise [gymnastika -- nude exercise] has taken hold on me. So, now that it is your turn, do not refuse to try a bout with me; it will be good for both of us.

Translator's note:
Sciron was a mighty man who attacked all who came near him and threw them from a cliff. He was overcome by Theseus. Antaeus, a terrible giant, forced all passersby to wrestle with him. He was invincible until Heracles crushed him in his arms.

~Plat. Theaet. 169a, translated by Fowler.











Here did the Hellenes, flushed with a victory granted by Ares
Over the routed Persians, together, for Hellas delivered,
Build them an altar of Zeus, Zeus as Deliverer known.

Plut. Arist. 19.6

Warrior Kosmos, Warrior Sanction
Ares Hypostatized: Manhood is God


Plato was strongly opposed to the prevailing a-moralism and hedonism of his age.

He searched, says Shorey, for

arguments that would convince, or at least confute, the ethical nihilism of a war-weary, cynical and over-enlightened generation -- for proof, in short, that virtue and happiness coincide.

~Introduction to Book II of Plato's Republic

In seeking to confute that nihilism, and to demonstrate the Virtue -- which, as we've seen, is rooted in Fighting Manhood -- and Happiness coincide, there was no way Plato could escape the fundamental postulates of his own culture -- which was a Warriordom; or of that culture's World of Being, a Warrior World of Being.

Suffused -- with Fighting Manhood.

Nor did he have any reason to wish to escape those postulates.

For they were not -- and are not -- dysfunctional.

To the contrary, it's the absence of manliness -- the want of Manhood -- which results in dysfunction, disorder, dis-harmony and dissonance.

For it is Manhood -- Fighting Manhood -- which gifts us with Order, Harmony, Discipline, and Restraint.